SUPPORT THE WORK

GetWiki

if and only if

ARTICLE SUBJECTS
aesthetics  →
being  →
complexity  →
database  →
enterprise  →
ethics  →
fiction  →
history  →
internet  →
knowledge  →
language  →
licensing  →
linux  →
logic  →
method  →
news  →
perception  →
philosophy  →
policy  →
purpose  →
religion  →
science  →
sociology  →
software  →
truth  →
unix  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE TYPES
essay  →
feed  →
help  →
system  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE ORIGINS
critical  →
discussion  →
forked  →
imported  →
original  →
if and only if
[ temporary import ]
please note:
- the content below is remote from Wikipedia
- it has been imported raw for GetWiki
{{Use dmy dates|date=February 2015}}{{Redirect|Iff|other uses|IFF (disambiguation)}}{{Redirect-distinguish|↔|Bidirectional traffic}}{{refimprove|date=July 2013}}Logical symbols representing iff}}In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, if and only if (shortened iff) is a biconditional logical connective between statements.In that it is biconditional (a statement of material equivalence),BOOK, Copi, I. M., Cohen, C., Flage, D. E., 2006, Essentials of Logic, Second, Upper Saddle River, NJ, Pearson Education, 197, 978-0-13-238034-8, the connective can be likened to the standard material conditional ("only if", equal to "if ... then") combined with its reverse ("if"); hence the name. The result is that the truth of either one of the connected statements requires the truth of the other (i.e. either both statements are true, or both are false). It is controversial whether the connective thus defined is properly rendered by the English "if and only if", with its pre-existing meaning. There is nothing to stop one from stipulating that we may read this connective as "only if and if", although this may lead to confusion.In writing, phrases commonly used, with debatable propriety, as alternatives to P "if and only if" Q include Q is necessary and sufficient for P, P is equivalent (or materially equivalent) to Q (compare material implication), P precisely if Q, P precisely (or exactly) when Q, P exactly in case Q, and P just in case Q.Weisstein, Eric W. "Iff." From MathWorld--A Wolfram Web Resource.weblink Some authors regard "iff" as unsuitable in formal writing;E.g. {{citation|title=Reading, Writing, and Proving: A Closer Look at Mathematics|series=Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics|first1=Ulrich|last1=Daepp|first2=Pamela|last2=Gorkin|publisher=Springer|year=2011|isbn=9781441994790|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4QKcaXrVZb0C&pg=PA52|page=52|quote=While it can be a real time-saver, we don't recommend it in formal writing.}} others use it freely.{{citation|title=Engineering Writing by Design: Creating Formal Documents of Lasting Value|first1=Edward J.|last1=Rothwell|first2=Michael J.|last2=Cloud|publisher=CRC Press|year=2014|isbn=9781482234312|page=98|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=muXMAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA98|quote=It is common in mathematical writing}}.In logical formulae, logical symbols are used instead of these phrases; see the discussion of notation.

Definition

The truth table of P Leftrightarrow Q is as follows:p q. Wolfram|Alpha{{citation|title=If and only if|first1=|last1=|first2=|last2=|publisher=UHM Department of Mathematics|year=|isbn=|page=|url=http://www.math.hawaii.edu/~ramsey/Logic/Iff.html|quote=Theorems which have the form "P if and only Q" are much prized in mathematics. They give what are called "necessary and sufficient" conditions, and give completely equivalent and hopefully interesting new ways to say exactly the same thing.}}.{| class="wikitable" style="margin:1em auto; text-align:center; float:left"|+ Truth table! scope="col" style="width:20%" | P! scope="col" style="width:20%" | Q! scope="col" style="width:20%" | {{nowrap|P Rightarrow Q}}! scope="col" style="width:20%" | {{nowrap|P Leftarrow Q}}! scope="col" style="width:20%" | {{nowrap|P Leftrightarrow Q}}
| T
F style="background:papayawhip" F
F T T style="background:papayawhip" F
F style="background:papayawhip" | T
{{clear}}It is equivalent to that produced by the XNOR gate, and opposite to that produced by the XOR gate.

Usage

Notation

The corresponding logical symbols are "↔", "Leftrightarrow", and "≡", and sometimes "iff". These are usually treated as equivalent. However, some texts of mathematical logic (particularly those on first-order logic, rather than propositional logic) make a distinction between these, in which the first, ↔, is used as a symbol in logic formulas, while ⇔ is used in reasoning about those logic formulas (e.g., in metalogic). In Łukasiewicz's notation, it is the prefix symbol 'E'.Another term for this logical connective is exclusive nor.

Proofs

In most logical systems, one proves a statement of the form "P iff Q" by proving "if P, then Q" and "if Q, then P". Proving this pair of statements sometimes leads to a more natural proof since there are not obvious conditions in which one would infer a biconditional directly. An alternative is to prove the disjunction "(P and Q) or (not-P and not-Q)", which itself can be inferred directly from either of its disjuncts—that is, because "iff" is truth-functional, "P iff Q" follows if P and Q have both been shown true, or both false.

Origin of iff and pronunciation

Usage of the abbreviation "iff" first appeared in print in John L. Kelley's 1955 book General Topology.General Topology, reissue {{ISBN|978-0-387-90125-1}}Its invention is often credited to Paul Halmos, who wrote "I invented 'iff,' for 'if and only if'—but I could never believe I was really its first inventor."BOOK, Nicholas J. Higham, Handbook of writing for the mathematical sciences,weblink 1998, SIAM, 978-0-89871-420-3, 24, 2nd, It is somewhat unclear how "iff" was meant to be pronounced. In current practice, the single 'word' "iff" is almost always read as the four words "if and only if." However, in the preface of General Topology, Kelley suggests that it should be read differently: "In some cases where mathematical content requires 'if and only if' and euphony demands something less I use Halmos' 'iff'". The authors of one discrete mathematics textbook suggest:BOOK, Discrete Algorithmic Mathematics, Maurer, Stephen B., Ralston, Anthony, CRC Press, 2005, 1568811667, 3rd, Boca Raton, Fla., 60, "Should you need to pronounce iff, really hang on to the 'ff' so that people hear the difference from 'if'", implying that "iff" could be pronounced as /ɪfː/.

Usage in definitions

Technically, definitions are always "if and only if" statements and many texts like Kelley's General Topology follow the strict demands of logic and use "if and only if" or iff in definitions of new terms (for instance, from General Topology, p. 25: "A set is countable iff it is finite or countably infinite" [boldface in original]). However, this usage of "if and only if" is not universal and often, mathematical definitions follow the special convention that "if" is interpreted to mean "if and only if" (for example, one might say, "A topological space is compact if every open cover has a finite subcover").{{citation|page=71|first=Steven G.|last=Krantz|title=A Primer of Mathematical Writing|year=1996|publisher=American Mathematical Society|isbn=978-0-8218-0635-7}}

Distinction from "if" and "only if"

{{unreferenced section|date=June 2013}}
  1. "Madison will eat the fruit if it is an apple." (equivalent to "Only if Madison will eat the fruit, it is an apple;" or "Madison will eat the fruit ← fruit is an apple")
  2. : This states that Madison will eat fruits that are apples. It does not, however, exclude the possibility that Madison might also eat bananas or other types of fruit. All that is known for certain is that she will eat any and all apples that she happens upon. That the fruit is an apple is a sufficient condition for Madison to eat the fruit.
  3. "Madison will eat the fruit only if it is an apple." (equivalent to "If Madison will eat the fruit, then it is an apple" or "Madison will eat the fruit → fruit is an apple")
  4. : This states that the only fruit Madison will eat is an apple. It does not, however, exclude the possibility that Madison will refuse an apple if it is made available, in contrast with (1), which requires Madison to eat any available apple. In this case, that a given fruit is an apple is a necessary condition for Madison to be eating it. It is not a sufficient condition since Madison might not eat all the apples she is given.
  5. "Madison will eat the fruit if and only if it is an apple" (equivalent to "Madison will eat the fruit ↔ fruit is an apple")
  6. : This statement makes it clear that Madison will eat all and only those fruits that are apples. She will not leave any apple uneaten, and she will not eat any other type of fruit. That a given fruit is an apple is both a necessary and a sufficient condition for Madison to eat the fruit.
Sufficiency is the converse of necessity. That is to say, given P→Q (i.e. if P then Q), P would be a sufficient condition for Q, and Q would be a necessary condition for P. Also, given P→Q, it is true that ¬Q→¬P (where ¬ is the negation operator, i.e. "not"). This means that the relationship between P and Q, established by P→Q, can be expressed in the following, all equivalent, ways:
P is sufficient for Q Q is necessary for P ¬Q is sufficient for ¬P ¬P is necessary for ¬Q
As an example, take (1), above, which states P→Q, where P is "the fruit in question is an apple" and Q is "Madison will eat the fruit in question". The following are four equivalent ways of expressing this very relationship:
If the fruit in question is an apple, then Madison will eat it. Only if Madison will eat the fruit in question, is it an apple. If Madison will not eat the fruit in question, then it is not an apple. Only if the fruit in question is not an apple, will Madison not eat it.
So we see that (2), above, can be restated in the form of if...then as "If Madison will eat the fruit in question, then it is an apple"; taking this in conjunction with (1), we find that (3) can be stated as "If the fruit in question is an apple, then Madison will eat it; and if Madison will eat the fruit, then it is an apple".

In terms of Euler diagrams

File:Example of A is a proper subset of B.svg|A is a proper subset of B. A number is in A only if it is in B; a number is in B if it is in A.File:Example of C is no proper subset of B.svg|C is a subset but not a proper subset of B. A number is in B if and only if it is in C, and a number is in C if and only if it is in B.Euler diagrams show logical relationships among events, properties, and so forth. "P only if Q", "if P then Q", and "P→Q" all mean that P is a subset, either proper or improper, of Q. "P if Q", "if Q then P", and Q→P all mean that Q is a proper or improper subset of P. "P if and only if Q" and "Q if and only if P" both mean that the sets P and Q are identical to each other.

More general usage

Iff is used outside the field of logic. Wherever logic is applied, especially in mathematical discussions, it has the same meaning as above: it is an abbreviation for if and only if, indicating that one statement is both necessary and sufficient for the other. This is an example of mathematical jargon. (However, as noted above, if, rather than iff, is more often used in statements of definition.)The elements of X are all and only the elements of Y is used to mean: "for any z in the domain of discourse, z is in X if and only if z is in Y."

See also

References

{{Reflist|30em}}

External links



- content above as imported from Wikipedia
- "if and only if" does not exist on GetWiki (yet)
- time: 8:52pm EDT - Sat, Jul 21 2018
[ this remote article is provided by Wikipedia ]
LATEST EDITS [ see all ]
GETWIKI 09 MAY 2016
GETWIKI 18 OCT 2015
M.R.M. Parrott
Biographies
GETWIKI 20 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 19 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 18 AUG 2014
Wikinfo
Culture
CONNECT