SUPPORT THE WORK

GetWiki

human nature

ARTICLE SUBJECTS
aesthetics  →
being  →
complexity  →
database  →
enterprise  →
ethics  →
fiction  →
history  →
internet  →
knowledge  →
language  →
licensing  →
linux  →
logic  →
method  →
news  →
perception  →
philosophy  →
policy  →
purpose  →
religion  →
science  →
sociology  →
software  →
truth  →
unix  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE TYPES
essay  →
feed  →
help  →
system  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE ORIGINS
critical  →
discussion  →
forked  →
imported  →
original  →
human nature
[ temporary import ]
please note:
- the content below is remote from Wikipedia
- it has been imported raw for GetWiki
{{Other uses}}(File:Pioneer plaque humans.svg|thumb|Human figures on NASA pioneer plaques. Credit: NASA Ames)Human nature is a bundle of characteristics, including ways of thinking, feeling, and acting, which humans are said to have naturally.WEB,weblink Definition of HUMAN NATURE, www.merriam-webster.com, WEB,weblink human nature, WEB,weblink the definition of human nature, Dictionary.com, WEB,weblink human nature Meaning in the Cambridge English Dictionary, dictionary.cambridge.org, The term is often regarded as capturing what it is to be human, or the essence of humanity. The term is controversial because it is disputed whether or not such an essence exists. Arguments about human nature have been a mainstay of philosophy for centuries and the concept continues to provoke lively philosophical debate.BOOK, 2018-07-19, Hannon, Elizabeth, Lewens, Tim, Why We Disagree About Human Nature, Oxford Scholarship Online, 1, 10.1093/oso/9780198823650.001.0001, 9780198823650, JOURNAL, Kronfeldner, Maria, Roughley, Neil, Toepfer, Georg, September 2014, Recent Work on Human Nature: Beyond Traditional Essences, Philosophy Compass, 9, 9, 642–652, 10.1111/phc3.12159, 1747-9991, BOOK, Arguing About Human Nature: Contemporary Debates, Routledge, 2013, 978-0415894401, Downes, Stephen M., London, Machery, Edouard, The concept also continues to play a role in science, with neuroscientists, psychologists and social scientists sometimes claiming that their results have yielded insight into human nature.JOURNAL, Ramachandran, V. S., 1996, What neurological syndromes can tell us about human nature: some lessons from phantom limbs, capgras syndrome, and anosognosia, Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology, 61, 115–134, 0091-7451, 9246441, 10.1101/SQB.1996.061.01.015, JOURNAL, Blank, Robert H., 2002, Review of Jean-Pierre Changeux and Paul Ricoeur. 2000. What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain, The American Journal of Bioethics: AJOB, 2, 4, 69–70, 10.1162/152651602320957718, 1536-0075, 22494253, JOURNAL, Fowler, James H., Schreiber, Darren, 2008-11-07, Biology, politics, and the emerging science of human nature, Science, 322, 5903, 912–914, 10.1126/science.1158188, 1095-9203, 18988845, JOURNAL, Paulson, Steve, Berlin, Heather A., Miller, Christian B., Shermer, Michael, 2016, The moral animal: virtue, vice, and human nature, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1384, 1, 39–56, 10.1111/nyas.13067, 1749-6632, 27248691, Human nature is traditionally contrasted with characteristics that vary among humans, such as characteristics associated with specific cultures. Debates about human nature are related to, although not the same as, debates about the comparative importance of genes and environment in development ("nature versus nurture").

Overview

The concept of nature as a standard by which to make judgments is traditionally said to have begun in Greek philosophy, at least as regards the Western and Middle Eastern languages and perspectives which are heavily influenced by it."Progress or Refurn" in An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays by Leo Strauss. (Expanded version of Political Philosophy: Six Essays by Leo Strauss, 1975.) Ed. Hilail Gilden. Detroit: Wayne State UP, 1989.The teleological approach of Aristotle came to be dominant by late classical and medieval times. By this account, human nature really causes humans to become what they become, and so it exists somehow independently of individuals. This in turn has been understood as also showing a special connection between human nature and divinity. This approach understands human nature in terms of final and formal causes. In other words, nature itself (or a nature-creating divinity) has intentions and goals, similar somehow to human intentions and goals, and one of those goals is humanity living naturally. Such understandings of human nature see this nature as an "idea", or "form" of a human.Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1078b.However, the existence of this invariable and metaphysical human nature is subject of much historical debate, continuing into modern times. Against this idea of a fixed human nature, the relative malleability of man has been argued especially strongly in recent centuries—firstly by early modernists such as Thomas Hobbes and Jean-Jacques Rousseau. In Rousseau's Emile, or On Education, Rousseau wrote: "We do not know what our nature permits us to be".ENCYCLOPAEDIA, 1995, Encyclopædia Britannica, Saunders, Jason Lewis,weblink Western Philosophical Schools and Doctrines: Ancient and Medieval Schools: Sophists: Particular Doctrines: Theoretical issues, 7 February 2011, yes,weblink" title="web.archive.org/web/20110527020558weblink">weblink 27 May 2011, Since the early 19th century, thinkers such as Hegel, Marx, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Sartre, structuralists, and postmodernists have also sometimes argued against a fixed or innate human nature.Charles Darwin's theory of evolution has changed the nature of the discussion, supporting the proposition that mankind's ancestors were not like mankind today. Still more recent scientific perspectives—such as behaviorism, determinism, and the chemical model within modern psychiatry and psychology—claim to be neutral regarding human nature. As in much of modern science, such disciplines seek to explain with little or no recourse to metaphysical causation.WEB, TELEOLOGICAL REALISM IN BIOLOGY,weblink www.academia.edu, 2016-02-23, They can be offered to explain the origins of human nature and its underlying mechanisms, or to demonstrate capacities for change and diversity which would arguably violate the concept of a fixed human nature.

Classical Greek philosophy

Philosophy in classical Greece is the ultimate origin{{citation needed|date=October 2016}} of the Western conception of the nature of a thing. According to Aristotle, the philosophical study of human nature itself originated with Socrates, who turned philosophy from study of the heavens to study of the human things.Aristotle's Metaphysics Socrates is said to have studied the question of how a person should best live, but he left no written works. It is clear from the works of his students Plato and Xenophon, and also by what was said about him by Aristotle (Plato's student), that Socrates was a rationalist and believed that the best life and the life most suited to human nature involved reasoning. The Socratic school was the dominant surviving influence in philosophical discussion in the Middle Ages, amongst Islamic, Christian, and Jewish philosophers.The human soul in the works of Plato and Aristotle has a divided nature, divided in a specifically human way. One part is specifically human and rational, and divided into a part which is rational on its own, and a spirited part which can understand reason. Other parts of the soul are home to desires or passions similar to those found in animals. In both Aristotle and Plato, spiritedness (thumos) is distinguished from the other passions (epithumiai).Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics Book I and VI; Plato Republic Book IV. The proper function of the "rational" was to rule the other parts of the soul, helped by spiritedness. By this account, using one's reason is the best way to live, and philosophers are the highest types of humans.Aristotle—Plato's most famous student—made some of the most famous and influential statements about human nature. In his works, apart from using a similar scheme of a divided human soul, some clear statements about human nature are made:
  • Man is a conjugal animal, meaning an animal which is born to couple when an adult, thus building a household (oikos) and, in more successful cases, a clan or small village still run upon patriarchal lines.Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, VIII. 1162a; Politics 1252a.
  • Man is a political animal, meaning an animal with an innate propensity to develop more complex communities the size of a city or town, with a division of labor and law-making. This type of community is different in kind from a large family, and requires the special use of human reason.Aristotle, Politics 1252b.
  • Man is a mimetic animal. Man loves to use his imagination (and not only to make laws and run town councils). He says "we enjoy looking at accurate likenesses of things which are themselves painful to see, obscene beasts, for instance, and corpses." And the "reason why we enjoy seeing likenesses is that, as we look, we learn and infer what each is, for instance, 'that is so and so.{{'"}}Aristotle, Poetics 1148b.
For Aristotle, reason is not only what is most special about humanity compared to other animals, but it is also what we were meant to achieve at our best. Much of Aristotle's description of human nature is still influential today. However, the particular teleological idea that humans are "meant" or intended to be something has become much less popular in modern times.Aristotle, The Politics of Aristotle: With an Introduction, Two Prefactory Essays and Notes Critical and Explanatory, Clarendon Press, 1887, Pg. 189–190For the Socratics, human nature, and all natures, are metaphysical concepts. Aristotle developed the standard presentation of this approach with his theory of four causes. Every living thing exhibits four aspects or "causes": matter, form, effect, and end. For example, an oak tree is made of plant cells (matter), grew from an acorn (effect), exhibits the nature of oak trees (form), and grows into a fully mature oak tree (end). Human nature is an example of a formal cause, according to Aristotle. Likewise, to become a fully actualized human being (including fully actualizing the mind) is our end. Aristotle (Nicomachean Ethics, Book X) suggests that the human intellect (νούς) is "smallest in bulk" but the most significant part of the human psyche, and should be cultivated above all else. The cultivation of learning and intellectual growth of the philosopher, which is thereby also the happiest and least painful life.

Chinese philosophy

Confucianism

File:Half Portraits of the Great Sage and Virtuous Men of Old - Meng Ke (å­Ÿè»»).jpg|thumb|Portrait of MenciusMenciusHuman nature is a central question in Chinese philosophy.Tang, Paul C.; Basafa, N. (1988). "Human Nature in Chinese Thought: A Wittgensteinian Treatment." Proceedings of the 12th International Wittgenstein Symposium 1988. From the Song dynasty, the theory of potential or innate goodness of human beings became dominant in Confucianism.Yen, Hung-Chung. "Human Nature and Learning in Ancient China." Education as Cultivation in Chinese Culture. Springer Singapore, 2015. 19-43.Mencius understood human nature as an ideal state that's expected to be formed under the right conditions or perhaps the innate tendency to this state. He argues that human nature is good.WEB, Van Norden, Bryan, Mencius,weblink The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, 3 December 2014, Therefore, humans have the capacity to be good, even though they are not all good. In Mencius' view, goodness is the result of the development of innate tendencies toward benevolence, righteousness, wisdom, and propriety. These tendencies are manifested in moral emotions. These manifestations can develop into virtues if people engage in reflection of it. Reflection brings recognition that virtue takes precedence over satisfaction, but a lack of reflection inhibits moral development.BOOK, Wong, David, Chinese Ethics,weblink The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, 14 September 2018, In other words, humans have a constitution comprising emotional predispositions that direct them to goodness. Mencius and his contemporaries also hold that the nature of the subject is the characteristic of the subject when given a healthy environment for the subject. Hence, Mencius claims that humans have a tendency to become good if they are raised in a healthy environment.
Mencius also addresses the question why the capacity for evil is not grounded in human nature. It is not the function of ears and eyes (i.e., sensory organs associated with sensual desires) but the function of the heart to reflect. People can be misled and led astray by their desires if they do not engage their ethical motivations. Therefore, if an individual becomes bad, it is not the result of his or her constitution. Mencius considers core virtues—humanity, justice, propriety, and wisdom—as internal qualities that humans originally possess, so people can not attain full satisfaction by solely pursuits of self-interest due to their innate morality.Xunzi understood human nature as the basic faculties, capacities, and desires that people have from birth.BOOK, Goldin, Paul R., Xunzi,weblink The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, 6 July 2018, He argues that human nature is evil and that any goodness is the result of human activity.JOURNAL, Moody, Peter R., Rational Choice Analysis In Classical Chinese Political Thought: The "Han Feizi", Polity, January 2008, 40, 1, 10.1057/palgrave.polity.2300068, 104–106, It is human nature to seek profit, because humans desire for sensory satisfaction. However, Xuzi states: "Now the nature of man is evil. It must depend on teachers and laws to become correct and achieve propriety and righteousness and then it becomes disciplined." He underscores that goodness comes from the traits and habits acquired through conscious actions, which he calls artifice (偽). Therefore, morality is seen as a human artifice but not as a part of human nature.BOOK, Puett, Michael J., The Ambivalence of Creation: Debates Concerning Innovation and Artifice in Early China, 2001, Stanford University Press, 978-0-8047-3623-7, 65, Mencius sees ritual (i.e., the standard for how humans should treat and interact with each other) as an outward expression of the inherent moral sense in human nature.JOURNAL, Moody, Peter R., Rational Choice Analysis In Classical Chinese Political Thought: The "Han Feizi", Polity, January 2008, 40, 1, 10.1057/palgrave.polity.2300068, 102–103, Xunzi agrees that humans have a moral sense, but he sees it as evidence for the badness in people. People namely desire what they lack, in which the human desire for goodness is an indication for the lack of goodness.

Legalism

File:Statue of Shang Yang.jpg|thumb|Statue of Shang YangShang YangHuman nature is one of the major foundations of Legalism in China.Legalists see the overwhelming majority of human beings as selfish in nature. They hold the view that human nature is evil, in which individuals are driven by selfishness. Therefore, people are not expected to always behave morally. For instance, due to the corrupt nature of humans, Legalists did not trust that officials would carry out their duties in a fair and impartial manner.BOOK, Duiker, William J., Spielvogel, Jackson J., World History, Volume I: To 1800, Wadsworth Cengage, 978-0-495-56902-2, 79, 6th, China in Antiquity, 2008-12-26, As social life is characterized by conflict among contending human actors and interests, there is a perpetual political struggle in which individuals are easily tempted due to their selfish interests at the expense of others.BOOK, Fu, Zhengyuan, China's legalists: The earliest totalitarians and their art of ruling, 1996, M.E. Sharpe, 978-1-56324-779-8, 82, However, Legalists do not consider whether human goodness or badness is inborn as well as whether human beings possess the fundamental qualities associated with that nature.According to Legalism, selfishness in human nature can not be eliminated or altered by education or self-cultivation. Legalists dismiss the possibility that people can overcome their selfishness and consider the possibility that people can be driven by moral commitment for others to be exceptionally rare. They do not consider the individual morality of both the rulers or the ruled to be an important concern in a political system. Instead, Legalist thinkers such as Han Fei emphasize clear and impersonal norms and standards (such as laws, regulations, and rules) as the basis to maintain order.BOOK, Pines, Yuri, Legalism in Chinese Philosophy,weblink The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, 16 November 2018, Legalists posit that human selfishness can become an asset rather than a threat to a state. Herein, individuals must be allowed to pursue their selfish interests in a manner that benefits rather than contradicts the needs of a state. Therefore, a political system that presupposes this human selfishness is the only viable system, wherein its actors (such as ministers and other officials) must be controlled and checked. Legalists view the usage of reward and punishment as effective political controls, because they consider that such aspects underlie human nature. According to the Legalist statesman Shang Yang, it is crucial to investigate the disposition of people in terms of rewards and penalties when a law is established. He further explains that a populace can not be driven to pursuits of agriculture or warfare if people consider these to be bitter or dangerous on the basis of calculations about their possible benefits, but people can be directed toward these pursuits through the application of positive and negative incentives.

Christian theology

In Christian theology, there are two ways of "conceiving human nature". The first is "spiritual, Biblical, and theistic", whereas the second is "natural, cosmical, and anti-theistic".John Tulloch, Christian Doctrine of Sin (Scribner, Armstrong, 1876), 6. The focus in this section is on the former. As William James put it in his study of human nature from a religious perspective, "religion" has a "department of human nature".William James, The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature (The Modern Library, 1902), 473.Various views of human nature have been held by theologians. However, there are some "basic assertions" in all "biblical anthropology".Justo L. González, Essential Theological Terms s.v. "Anthropoology" (Westminster John Knox, 2005), 8.
  1. "Humankind has its origin in God, its creator."
  2. "Humans bear the 'image of God'."
  3. Humans are "to rule the rest of creation".
The Bible contains no single "doctrine of human nature". Rather, it provides material for more philosophical descriptions of human nature.Kevin J. Vanhoozer, gen. ed., Dictionary for Theological Interpretation of the Bible (Baker, 2005), s.v. "Human Being, Doctrine of," 310. For example, Creation as found in the Book of Genesis provides a theory on human nature.WEB, Kenneth, Ackerman, Anthropology and Human Nature, 13,weblink Catechism of the Catholic ChurchWEB,weblink Catechism of the Catholic Church - IntraText, www.vatican.va, in chapter "Dignity of the human person" has article about man as image of God, vocation to beatitude, freedom, human acts, passions, moral conscience, virtues and sin.

Created human nature

As originally created, the Bible describes "two elements" in human nature: "the body and the breath or spirit of life breathed into it by God". By this was created a "living soul", that is, a "living person".Louis Berkhof, Systematic Theology (Eerdmans, 1996), 183. According to Genesis 1:27, this living person was made in the "image of God".WEB,weblink Genesis Chapter 1 (NIV), From the biblical perspective, "to be human is to bear the image of God".Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 18.Genesis does not elaborate the meaning of "the image of God", but scholars find suggestions. One is that being created in the image of God distinguishes human nature from that of the beasts.Kevin J. Vanhoozer, gen. ed., Dictionary for Theological Interpretation of the Bible (Baker, 2005), s. v. "Image of God," 318-319. Another is that as God is "able to make decisions and rule" so humans made in God's image are "able to make decisions and rule". A third is that mankind possesses an inherent ability "to set goals" and move toward them.Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 5, 14. That God denoted creation as "good" suggests that Adam was "created in the image of God, in righteousness."James Wood, A Dictionary of the Holy Bible (Griffin and Rudd, 1813), 34.Adam was created with ability to make "right choices", but also with the ability to choose sin, by which he fell from righteousness into a state of "sin and depravity".Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 231. Thus, according to the Bible, "humankind is not as God created it".Malcolm Jeeves, Human Nature: Reflections on the Integration of Psychology and Christianity (Templeton ,2006), 115.

Fallen human nature

By Adam's fall into sin, "human nature" became "corrupt", although it retains the image of God. Both the Old Testament and the New Testament teach that "sin is universal".Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 17, 141. For example, Psalm 51:5 reads: "For behold I was conceived in iniquities; and in sins did my mother conceive me."{{Bibleref2|Psalm|51:5|KJV}} Jesus taught that everyone is a "sinner naturally" because it is mankind's "nature and disposition to sin".John Tulloch, Christian Doctrine of Sin (Scribner, Armstrong, 1876), 124-125. Paul, in Romans 7:18, speaks of his "sinful nature".WEB,weblink Romans 7:18. - - Bible Gateway, www.biblegateway.com, Such a "recognition that there is something wrong with the moral nature of man is found in all religions".Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 141. Augustine of Hippo coined a term for the assessment that all humans are born sinful: original sin.Kevin J. Vanhoozer, gen. ed., Dictionary for Theological Interpretation of the Bible (Baker, 2005), 312. Original sin is "the tendency to sin innate in all human beings"."original sin" in The Oxford Pocket Dictionary of Current English (Oxford University, 2009). The doctrine of original sin is held by the Catholic Church and most mainstream Protestant denominations, but rejected by the Eastern Orthodox Church, which holds the similar doctrine of ancestral fault."The corruption of original sin extends to every aspect of human nature": to "reason and will" as well as to "appetites and impulses". This condition is sometimes called "total depravity".Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 152. Total depravity does not mean that humanity is as "thoroughly depraved" as it could become.Louis Berkhof, Systematic Theology (Eerdmans, 1996), 246. Commenting on Romans 2:14, John Calvin writes that all people have "some notions of justice and rectitude ... which are implanted by nature" all people.BOOK, John, Calvin, Commentary on Romans, 2,weblink Adam embodied the "whole of human nature" so when Adam sinned "all of human nature sinned".Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 158. The Old Testament does not explicitly link the "corruption of human nature" to Adam's sin. However, the "universality of sin" implies a link to Adam. In the New Testament, Paul concurs with the "universality of sin". He also makes explicit what the Old Testament implied: the link between humanity's "sinful nature" and Adam's sinJames Hastings, ed., A Dictionary of the Bible: Pleroma-Zuzim (C. Scribner's Sons, 1902) s. v. "Sin," 528, 534. In Romans 5:19, Paul writes, "through [Adam's] disobedience humanity became sinful".WEB,weblink Bible Gateway passage: Romans 5:19 - GOD'S WORD Translation, Bible Gateway, Paul also applied humanity's sinful nature to himself: "there is nothing good in my sinful nature."WEB,weblink Romans 7:18 - NIRV - I know there is nothing good in my sinful natur..., Bible Study Tools, WEB,weblink Sarx - New Testament Greek Lexicon - New American Standard, Bible Study Tools, The theological "doctrine of original sin" as an inherent element of human nature is not based only on the Bible. It is in part a "generalization from obvious facts" open to empirical observation.John Tulloch, Christian Doctrine of Sin (Scribner, Armstrong, 1876), 175.

Empirical view

A number of experts on human nature have described the manifestations of original (i.e., the innate tendency to) sin as empirical facts.
  • Biologist Richard Dawkins in his The Selfish Gene states that "a predominant quality" in a successful surviving gene is "ruthless selfishness". Furthermore, "this gene selfishness will usually give rise to selfishness in individual behavior".Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (Oxford University, 1989), 2-3.
  • Child psychologist Burton L. White, PhD,WEB,weblink Dr. Burton White, 84, believed children should avoid day care - The Boston Globe, finds a "selfish" trait in children from birth, a trait that expresses itself in actions that are "blatantly selfish."Burton L. White, Raising a Happy, Unspoiled Child (Touchstone; Rev ed, 1995), 98, 269.
  • Sociologist William Graham Sumner finds it a fact that "everywhere one meets "fraud, corruption, ignorance, selfishness, and all the other vices of human nature".BOOK, William Graham Sumner, The Challenge of Facts and Other Essays, Yale University, 1914, 233,weblink He enumerates "the vices and passions of human nature" as "cupidity, lust, vindictiveness, ambition, and vanity". Sumner finds such human nature to be universal: in all people, in all places, and in all stations in society.BOOK, What Social Classes Owe to Each Other'', Harper & Brothers, 1883,weblink
  • Psychiatrist Thomas Anthony Harris, MD, on the basis of his "data at hand", observes "sin, or badness, or evil, or 'human nature', whatever we call the flaw in our species, is apparent in every person". Harris calls this condition "intrinsic badness" or "original sin".Thomas A. Harris, I'm OK — You're OK (HarperCollins, 2004, Quill edition), 233.
Empirical discussion questioning the genetic exclusivity of such an intrinsic badness proposition is presented by researchers Elliott Sober and David Sloan Wilson. In their book, Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior, they propose a theory of multilevel group selection in support of an inherent genetic "altruism" in opposition to the original sin exclusivity for human nature.Elliott Sober and David Sloan Wilson, Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998, 394 pp., {{ISBN|0-674-93046-0}}

20th century Liberal Theology

Liberal theologians in the early 20th century described human nature as "basically good", needing only "proper training and education". But the above examples document the return to a "more realistic view" of human nature "as basically sinful and self-centered". Human nature needs "to be regenerated ... to be able to live the unselfish life".Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 187-188.

Regenerated human nature

According to the Bible, "Adam's disobedience corrupted human nature" but God mercifully "regenerates".Walter A. Elwell, ed, Evangelical Dictionary of Theology (Baker, 2001), 399. "Regeneration is a radical change" that involves a "renewal of our [human] nature".Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 101. Thus, to counter original sin, Christianity purposes "a complete transformation of individuals" by Christ.Kevin J. Vanhoozer, gen. ed., Dictionary for Theological Interpretation of the Bible (Baker, 2005), 135, 313.The goal of Christ's coming is that fallen humanity might be "conformed to or transformed into the image of Christ who is the perfect image of God", as in 2 Corinthians 4:4.Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 21, 24. The New Testament makes clear the "universal need" for regeneration.Watson E. Mills, Roger Aubrey Bullard, eds, Mercer Dictionary of the Bible (Mercer University, 1990), 741. A sampling of biblical portrayals of regenerating human nature and the behavioral results follow.
*being "transformed by the renewing of your minds" (Romans 12:2)WEB,weblink Bible Gateway passage: Romans 12:2 - New Revised Standard Version, Bible Gateway, *being transformed from one's "old self" (or "old man") into a "new self" (or "new man") (Col.3:9-10)WEB,weblink Colossians Chapter 3 (NIV), *being transformed from people who "hate others" and "are hard to get along with" and who are "jealous, angry, and selfish" to people who are "loving, happy, peaceful, patient, kind, good, faithful, gentle, and self-controlled" (Galatians 5:20-23)WEB,weblink Bible Gateway passage: Galatians 5:20-23 - Contemporary English Version, Bible Gateway, *being transformed from looking "to your own interests" to looking "to the interests of others" (Philippians 2:4)WEB,weblink Bible Gateway passage: Philippians 2:4 - New Revised Standard Version, Bible Gateway,

Early modern philosophy

One of the defining changes that occurred at the end of the Middle Ages was the end of the dominance of Aristotelian philosophy, and its replacement by a new approach to the study of nature, including human nature.{{citation needed|date=October 2016}} In this approach, all attempts at conjecture about formal and final causes were rejected as useless speculation.{{citation needed|date=October 2016}} Also, the term "law of nature" now applied to any regular and predictable pattern in nature, not literally a law made by a divine lawmaker, and, in the same way, "human nature" became not a special metaphysical cause, but simply whatever can be said to be typical tendencies of humans.{{citation needed|date=October 2016}}Although this new realism applied to the study of human life from the beginning—for example, in Machiavelli's works—the definitive argument for the final rejection of Aristotle was associated especially with Francis Bacon. Bacon sometimes wrote as if he accepted the traditional four causes ("It is a correct position that "true knowledge is knowledge by causes". And causes again are not improperly distributed into four kinds: the material, the formal, the efficient, and the final") but he adapted these terms and rejected one of the three: But of these the final cause rather corrupts than advances the sciences, except such as have to do with human action. The discovery of the formal is despaired of. The efficient and the material (as they are investigated and received, that is, as remote causes, without reference to the latent process leading to the form) are but slight and superficial, and contribute little, if anything, to true and active science.WEB, Francis Bacon: Novum Organum (1620),weblink www.constitution.org, 2016-02-23, Book II, Section II, This line of thinking continued with René Descartes, whose new approach returned philosophy or science to its pre-Socratic focus upon non-human things. Thomas Hobbes, then Giambattista Vico, and David Hume all claimed to be the first to properly use a modern Baconian scientific approach to human things.Hobbes famously followed Descartes in describing humanity as matter in motion, just like machines. He also very influentially described man's natural state (without science and artifice) as one where life would be "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short".Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, XIII.9 Following him, John Locke's philosophy of empiricism also saw human nature as a tabula rasa. In this view, the mind is at birth a "blank slate" without rules, so data are added, and rules for processing them are formed solely by our sensory experiences.Locke, John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Kenneth P. Winkler (ed.), Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, IN, 1996, pp. 33–36.Jean-Jacques Rousseau pushed the approach of Hobbes to an extreme and criticized it at the same time. He was a contemporary and acquaintance of Hume, writing before the French Revolution and long before Darwin and Freud. He shocked Western civilization with his Second Discourse by proposing that humans had once been solitary animals, without reason or language or communities, and had developed these things due to accidents of pre-history. (This proposal was also less famously made by Giambattista Vico.) In other words, Rousseau argued that human nature was not only not fixed, but not even approximately fixed compared to what had been assumed before him. Humans are political, and rational, and have language now, but originally they had none of these things.Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, The Social Contract, Translated by Maurice Cranston, Published by Penguin Classics, 1968, {{ISBN|0-14-044201-4}}, pg. 136 This in turn implied that living under the management of human reason might not be a happy way to live at all, and perhaps there is no ideal way to live. Rousseau is also unusual in the extent to which he took the approach of Hobbes, asserting that primitive humans were not even naturally social. A civilized human is therefore not only imbalanced and unhappy because of the mismatch between civilized life and human nature, but unlike Hobbes, Rousseau also became well known for the suggestion that primitive humans had been happier, "noble savages".{{Citation |last=Velkley |first=Richard |title=Being after Rousseau: Philosophy and Culture in Question |year=2002 |publisher= University of Chicago Press}}Rousseau's conception of human nature has been seen as the origin of many intellectual and political developments of the 19th and 20th centuries.Delaney, James, Rousseau and the Ethics of Virtue, Continuum International Publishing Group, 2006, {{ISBN|0-8264-8724-6}}, pg. 49–52 He was an important influence upon Kant, Hegel, and Marx, and the development of German idealism, historicism, and romanticism.What human nature did entail, according to Rousseau and the other modernists of the 17th and 18th centuries, were animal-like passions that led humanity to develop language and reasoning, and more complex communities (or communities of any kind, according to Rousseau).In contrast to Rousseau, David Hume was a critic of the oversimplifying and systematic approach of Hobbes, Rousseau, and some others whereby, for example, all human nature is assumed to be driven by variations of selfishness. Influenced by Hutcheson and Shaftesbury, he argued against oversimplification. On the one hand, he accepted that, for many political and economic subjects, people could be assumed to be driven by such simple selfishness, and he also wrote of some of the more social aspects of "human nature" as something which could be destroyed, for example if people did not associate in just societies. On the other hand, he rejected what he called the "paradox of the sceptics", saying that no politician could have invented words like {{"'}}honourable' and 'shameful,' 'lovely' and 'odious,' 'noble' and 'despicable{{'"}}, unless there was not some natural "original constitution of the mind".An Enquiry into the Sources of Morals Section 5.1Hume—like Rousseau—was controversial in his own time for his modernist approach, following the example of Bacon and Hobbes, of avoiding consideration of metaphysical explanations for any type of cause and effect. He was accused of being an atheist. He wrote: After Rousseau and Hume, the nature of philosophy and science changed, branching into different disciplines and approaches, and the study of human nature changed accordingly. Rousseau's proposal that human nature is malleable became a major influence upon international revolutionary movements of various kinds, while Hume's approach has been more typical in Anglo-Saxon countries, including the United States.{{citation needed|date=December 2017}}

Contemporary philosophy

The concept of human nature is a source of ongoing debate in contemporary philosophy, specifically within philosophy of biology, a subfield of the philosophy of science. Prominent critics of the concept – David L. Hull,JOURNAL, Hull, David L., January 1986, On Human Nature, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1986, 2, 3–13, 10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1986.2.192787, 0270-8647, Michael Ghiselin,BOOK, Metaphysics and the origins of species, Ghiselin, Michael T., State University of New York Press, 1997, Albany, and David Buller;BOOK, Adapting minds, Buller, David J., MIT Press, 2005, Cambridge, MA, see also – argue that human nature is incompatible with modern evolutionary biology. Conversely, defenders of the concept argue that when defined in certain ways, human nature is both scientifically respectable and meaningful. Therefore, the value and usefulness of the concept depends essentially on how one construes it. This section summarizes the prominent construals of human nature and outlines the key arguments from philosophers on both sides of the debate.

Criticism of the concept of human nature

Philosopher of science David L. Hull has influentially argued that there is no such thing as human nature. Hull's criticism is raised against philosophers who conceive human nature as a set of intrinsic phenotypic traits (or characters) that are universal among humans, unique to humans, and definitive of what it is to be a member of the biological species Homo sapiens. In particular, Hull argues that such "essential sameness of human beings" is "temporary, contingent and relatively rare" in biology. He argues that variation, insofar as it is the result of evolution, is an essential feature of all biological species. Moreover, the type of variation which characterizes a certain species in a certain historical moment is "to a large extent accidental". He writes:Periodically a biological species might be characterized by one or more characters which are both universally distributed among and limited to the organisms belonging to that species, but such states of affairs are temporary, contingent and relatively rare.{{rp|3}}Hull reasons that properties universally shared by all members of a certain species are usually also possessed by members of other species, whereas properties exclusively possessed by the members of a certain species are rarely possessed by all members of that species. For these reasons, Hull observes that, in contemporary evolutionary taxonomy, belonging to a particular species does not depend on the possession of any specific intrinsic properties. Rather, it depends on standing in the right kind of relations (relations of genealogy or interbreeding, depending on the precise species concept being used) to other members of the species. Consequently, there can be no intrinsic properties that define what it is to be a member of the species Homo sapiens. Individual organisms, including humans, are part of a species by virtue of their relations with other members of the same species, not shared intrinsic properties. According to Hull, the moral significance of his argument lies in its impact on the biologically legitimate basis for the concept of "human rights". While its has long been argued that there is a sound basis for "human rights" in the idea that all human beings are essentially the same, should Hull's criticism works, such a basis – at least on a biological level – would disappear. Nevertheless, Hull does not perceive this to be a fundamental for human rights, because people can choose to continue respecting human rights even without sharing the same human nature.

Defences of the concept of human nature

Several contemporary philosophers have attempted to defend the notion of human nature against charges that it is incompatible with modern evolutionary biology by proposing alternative interpretations. They claim that the concept of human nature continues to bear relevance in the fields of neuroscience and biology. Many have proposed non-essentialist notions. Others have argued that, even if Darwinism has shown that any attempt to base species membership on "intrinsic essential properties" is untenable, essences can still be "relational" – this would be consistent with the interbreeding, ecological, and phylogenetic species concepts, which are accepted by modern evolutionary biology.JOURNAL, Okasha, Samir, 2002, Darwinian Metaphysics: Species and the Question of Essentialism, Synthese, 131, 2, 191–213, 10.1023/A:1015731831011, These attempts aim to make Darwinism compatible with a certain conception of human nature which is stable across time.

Machery's "nomological" account

Philosopher of science Edouard Machery has proposed that the above criticisms only apply to a specific definition (or "notion") of human nature, and not to "human nature in general". He distinguishes between two different notions:
  • An essentialist notion of human nature - "Human nature is the set of properties that are separately necessary and jointly sufficient for being a human". These properties are also usually considered as distinctive of human beings. They are also intrinsic to humans and inherent to their essence.JOURNAL, Machery, Edouard, June 2008, A Plea for Human Nature, Philosophical Psychology, 21, 3, 321–329, 10.1080/09515080802170119, 0951-5089,
  • A nomological notion of human nature - "Human nature is the set of properties that humans tend to possess as a result of the evolution of their species".
Machery clarifies that, to count as being "a result of evolution", a property must have an ultimate explanation in Ernst Mayr's sense. It must be possible to explain the trait as the product of evolutionary processes. Importantly, properties can count as part of human nature in the nomological sense even if they are not universal among humans and not unique to humans. In other words, nomological properties need not be necessary nor sufficient for being human. Instead, it is enough that these properties are shared by most humans, as a result of the evolution of their species – they "need to be typical".BOOK,weblink Doubling Down on the Nomological Notion of Human Nature, Machery, Edouard, 2018-07-19, Oxford University Press, 1, 10.1093/oso/9780198823650.003.0002, 9780191862267, Therefore, human nature in the nomological sense does not define what it is to be a member of the species Homo sapiens. Examples of properties that count as parts of human nature on the nomological definition include: being bipedal, having the capacity to speak, having a tendency towards biparental investment in children, having fear reactions to unexpected noises. Finally, since they are the product of evolution, properties belonging to the nomological notion of human nature are not fixed, but they can change over time.Machery agrees with biologists and others philosophers of biology that the essentialist notion of human nature is incompatible with modern evolutionary biology: we cannot explain membership in the human species by means of a definition or a set of properties. However, he maintains that this does not mean humans have no nature, because we can accept the nomological notion which is not a definitional notion. Therefore, we should think of human nature as the many properties humans have in common as a result of evolution.

Problems with the nomological account

Machery also highlights potential drawbacks of the nomological account. One is that the nomological notion is a watered-down notion that cannot perform many of the roles that the concept of human nature is expected to perform in science and philosophy. The properties endowed upon humans by the nomological account do not distinguish humans from other animals or define what it is to be human. Machery pre-empts this objection by claiming that the nomological concept of human nature still fulfils many roles. He highlights the importance of a conception which picks out what humans share in common which can be used to make scientific, psychological generalizations about human-beings. One advantage of such a conception is that it gives an idea of the traits displayed by the majority of human beings which can be explained in evolutionary terms.Another potential drawback is that the nomological account of human nature threatens to lead to the absurd conclusion that all properties of humans are parts of human nature. According to the nomological account, a trait is only part of human nature if it is a result of evolution. However, there is a sense in which all human traits are results of evolution. For example, the belief that water is wet is shared by all humans. However, this belief is only possible because we have, for example, evolved a sense of touch. It is difficult to separate traits which are the result of evolution and those which are not. Machery claims the distinction between proximate and ultimate explanation can do the work here: only some human traits can be given an ultimate explanation, he argues.According to the philosopher Richard Samuels the account of human nature is expected to fulfill the five following roles:
  • an organizing function that demarks a territory of scientific inquiry
  • a descriptive function that is traditionally understood as specifying properties that are universal across and unique to human being
  • a causal explanatory function that offers causal explanation for occurring human behaviours and features
  • a taxonomic function that specifies possessing human nature as a necessary and sufficient criterion for belonging to the human species
  • Invariances that assume the understanding that human nature is to some degree fixed, invariable or at least hard to change and stable across time.
Samuels objects that Machery's nomological account fails to deliver on the causal explanatory function, because it claims that superficial and co-varying properties are the essence of human nature. Thus, human nature cannot be the underlying cause of these properties and accordingly cannot fulfill its causal explanatory role.Philosopher Grant Ramsey also rejects Machery's nomological account. For him, defining human nature with respect to only universal traits fails to capture many important human characteristics.JOURNAL, Ramsey, Grant, December 2013, Human Nature in a Post-essentialist World, Philosophy of Science,weblink 80, 5, 983–993, 10.1086/673902, 0031-8248, ResearchGate, 2019-01-21, 10.1.1.462.7085, Ramsey quotes the anthropologist Clifford Geertz, who claims that "the notion that unless a cultural phenomenon is empirically universal it cannot reflect anything about the nature of man is about as logical as the notion that because sickle-cell anemia is, fortunately, not universal, it cannot tell us anything about human genetic processes. It is not whether phenomena are empirically common that is critical in science...but whether they can be made to reveal the enduring natural processes that underly them".BOOK, The Interpretation of Cultures, Geertz, Clifford, Basic Books, 1973, New York, 44, Following Geertz, Ramsey holds that the study of human nature should not rely exclusively on universal or near-universal traits. There are many idiosyncratic and particular traits of scientific interest. Machery's account of human nature cannot give an account to such differences between men and women as the nomological account only picks out the common features within a species. In this light, the female menstrual cycle which is a biologically an essential and useful feature cannot be included in a nomological account of human nature.Ramsey also objects that Machery uncritically adopts the innate-acquired dichotomy, distinguishing between human properties due to enculturation and those due to evolution. Ramsey objects that human properties do not just fall in one of the two categories, writing that "any organismic property is going to be due to both heritable features of the organism as well as the particular environmental features the organism happens to encounter during its life."

Samuels' "causal essentialist" account

Richard Samuels (in his article Science and Human Nature) proposes a causal essentialist view that "human nature should be identified with a suite of mechanisms, processes, and structures that causally explain many of the more superficial properties and regularities reliably associated with humanity".JOURNAL, Samuels, Richard, 2012, Science and Human Nature,weblink Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 70, 4887, 587–588, PhilPapers, 10.1017/S1358246112000021, 2079588, This view is "causal" because the mechanisms causally explain the superficial properties reliably associated with humanity by referencing the underlying causal structures the properties belong to. For example, it is true that the belief that water is wet is shared by all humans yet it is not in itself a significant aspect of human nature. Instead, the psychological process that lead us to assign the word "wetness" to water is a universal trait shared by all human beings. In this respect, the superficial belief that water is wet reveals an important causal psychological process which is widely shared by most human beings. The explanation is also "essentialist" because there is a core set of empirically discoverable cognitive mechanism that count as part of the human nature. According to Samuels, his view avoids the standard biological objections to human nature essentialism.Samuels argues that the theoretical roles of human nature includes: organizing role, descriptive functions, causal explanatory functions, taxonomic functions, and invariances.In comparison with traditional essentialist view, the "causal essentialist" view does not accomplish the taxonomic role of human nature (the role of defining what it is to be human). He claims however, that no conception could achieve this, as the fulfillment of the role would not survive evolutionary biologists’ objections (articulated above by in "Criticisms of the concept of human nature"). In comparison with Machery’s nomological conception, Samuels wants to restore the causal-explanatory function of human nature. He defines the essence of human nature as causal mechanisms and not as surface-level properties. For instance, on this view, linguistic behaviour is not part of human nature, but the cognitive mechanisms underpinning linguistic behaviour might count as part of human nature.

Ramsey's "life-history trait cluster" account

Grant Ramsey proposes an alternative account of human nature, which he names the "life-history trait cluster" account. This view stems from the recognition that the combination of a specific genetic constitution with a specific environment is not sufficient to determine how a life will go, i.e., whether one is rich, poor, dies old, dies young, etc. Many ‘life histories’ are possible for a given individual, each populated by a great number of traits. Ramsey defines his conception of human nature in reference to the “pattern of trait clusters within the totality of extant possible life-histories”. In other words, there are certain life histories, i.e., possible routes one's life can take, for example: being rich, being a PhD student, or getting ill. Ramsey underlines the patterns behind these possible routes by delving into the causes of these life histories. For example, one can make the following claim: “Humans sweat when they get exhausted" or one can also propose neurological claims such as “Humans secrete Adrenaline when they are in flight-fight mode.” This approach enables Ramsey to go beyond the superficial appearances and understand the similarities/differences between individuals in a deeper level which refers to the causal mechanisms (processes, structures and constraints etc.) which lie beneath them. Once we list all the possible life-histories of an individual, we can find these causal patterns and add them together to form the basis of individual nature.Ramsey's next argumentative manoeuvre is to point out that traits are not randomly scattered across potential life histories; there are patterns. “These patterns” he states “provide the basis for the notion of individual and human nature”.{{rp|987}} While one’s ‘individual nature’ consists of the pattern of trait clusters distributed across that individual’s set of possible life histories, Human Nature, Ramsey defines as “the pattern of trait clusters within the totality of extant human possible life histories”.{{rp|987}} Thus, if we were to combine all possible life histories of all individuals in existence we would have access to the trait distribution patterns that constitute human nature.Trait patterns, on Ramsey's account, can be captured in the form of conditional statements, such as "if female, you develop ovaries" or "if male, you develop testes". These statements will not be true of all humans. Ramsey contends that these statements capture part of human nature if they have a good balance of pervasiveness (many people satisfy the antecedent of the conditional statement), and robustness (many people who satisfy the antecedent go on to satisfy the consequent).

Human nature and human enhancement

The contemporary debate between so-called “bioconservatives” and “transhumanists” is directly related to the concept of human nature: transhumanists argue that "current human nature is improvable through the use of applied science and other rational methods". Bioconservatives believe that the costs outweigh the benefits: in particular, they present their position as a defense of human nature which, according to them, is threatened by human enhancement technologies. Although this debate is mainly of an ethical kind, it is deeply rooted in the different interpretations of human nature, human freedom, and human dignity (which, according to bioconservatives, is specific to human beings, while transhumanists think that it can be possessed also by posthumans). As explained by Allen Buchanan,JOURNAL, Buchanan, Allen, 2009, Human nature and enhancement, Bioethics, 23, 3, 141–150, 10.1111/j.1467-8519.2008.00633.x, 19161567, the literature against human enhancement is characterized by two main concerns: that "enhancement may alter or destroy human nature" and that "if enhancement alters or destroys human nature, this will undercut our ability to ascertain the good", as "the good is determined by our nature".
Bioconservatives include Jürgen Habermas,BOOK, The Future of Human Nature, Habermas, Jurgen, 2003, Leon Kass,JOURNAL, Kass, Leon, 2003, Happy Souls: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Perfection, The New Atlantis, 1, Francis Fukuyama,BOOK, Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology Revolution, Fukuyama, Francis, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2002, New York, and Bill McKibben.JOURNAL, Bostrom, Nick, 2005, In Defense of Posthuman Dignity, Bioethics, 19, 3, 202–14, 10.1111/j.1467-8519.2005.00437.x, 16167401, Some of the reasons why they oppose (certain forms of) human enhancement technology are to be found in the worry that such technology would be “dehumanizing” (as they would undermine the human dignity intrinsically built in our human nature). For instance, they fear that becoming “posthumans” could pose a threat to “ordinary” humansJOURNAL, G. Annas, L. Andrews, and R. Isasi, 2002, Protecting the Endangered Human: Toward an International Treaty Prohibiting Cloning and Inheritable Alterations., American Journal of Law and Medicine, 28, 2–3, 162, or be harmful to posthumans themselves.BOOK, Life, Liberty, and Defense of Dignity: The Challenge for Bioethics, Kass, Leon, Encounter Books, 2002, San Francisco, Jürgen Habermas makes the argument against the specific case of genetic modification of unborn children by their parents, referred to as “eugenic programming” by Habermas. His argument is two-folded: The most immediate threat is on the “ethical freedom” of programmed individuals, and the subsequent threat is on the viability of liberal democracy. Reasoning of the former can be formulated as the following: Genetic programming of desirable traits, capabilities and dispositions puts restrictions on a person’s freedom to choose a life of his own, to be the sole author of his existence. A genetically-programmed child may feel alienated from his identity, which is now irreversibly co-written by human agents other than himself. This feeling of alienation, resulted from“contingency of a life’s beginning that is not at [one’s] disposal,” makes it difficult for genetically-modified persons to perceive themselves as moral agents who can make ethical judgement freely and independently - that is, without any substantial or definitive interference from another agent. Habermas proposes a second threat - the undermining power of genetic programming on the viability of democracy. The basis of liberal democracy, Habermas rightfully claims, is the symmetrical and independent mutual recognition among free, equal and autonomous persons. Genetic programming jeopardizes this condition by irreversibly subjecting children to permanent dependence on their parents, thus depriving them of their perceived ability to be full citizens of the legal community. This fundamental modification to human relationship erodes the foundation of liberal democracy and puts its viability in danger.BOOK, The Future of Human Nature, Habermas, Jurgen, 2003, 60–66, The most famous proponent of transhumanism, on the other hand, is Oxford Swedish philosopher Nick Bostrom. According to Bostrom, "human enhancement technologies should be made widely available", as they would offer enormous potential for improving the lives of human beings, without "dehumanizing" them: for instance, improving their intellectual and physical capacities, or protecting them from suffering, illnesses, aging, and physical and cognitive shortcomings. In response to bioconservatives, transhumanists argue that expanding a person's "capability set" would increase her freedom of choice, rather than reducing it.Allen Buchanan has questioned the relevance of the concept of human nature to this debate. In "Human Nature and Enhancement", he argued that good but also bad characteristics are part of human nature, and that changing the "bad" ones does not necessarily imply that the "good" ones will be affected. Moreover, Buchanan argued that the way we evaluate the good is independent of human nature: in fact, we can "make coherent judgements about the defective aspects of human nature, and if those defects were readied this need not affect our ability to judge what is good". Buchanan's conclusion is that the debate on enhancement of human beings would be more fruitful if it was conducted without appealing to the concept of human nature.Tim Lewens presented a similar position: since the only notions of human nature which are compatible with biology offer "no ethical guidance in debates over enhancement", we should set the concept of human nature aside when debating about enhancement. On the other hand, "folk", neo-Aristotelian conceptions of human nature seem to have normative implications, but they have no basis in scientific research.JOURNAL, Lewens, Tim, 2012, Human Nature: The Very Idea, Philosophy & Technology, 25, 4, 459–474, 10.1007/s13347-012-0063-x, Grant Ramsey replied to these claims, arguing that his "life-history trait cluster" account allows the concept of human nature "to inform questions of human enhancement".JOURNAL, Ramsey, Grant, 2012, How Human Nature Can Inform Human Enhancement: a Commentary on Tim Lewens's Human Nature: the Very Idea, Philosophy and Technology, 25, 4, 479–483, 10.1007/s13347-012-0087-2, Appeals to nature often fall foul of the naturalistic fallacy, whereby certain capacities or traits are considered morally 'good' in virtue of their naturalness. The fallacy was initially introduced by G E Moore in 1903, who challenged philosopher's attempts to define good reductively, in terms of natural properties (such as desirable). Reliance on 'the natural' as a justification for resisting enhancement is criticised on several grounds by transhumanists, against the bioconservative motivation to preserve or protect 'human nature'.For example, Nick Bostrom asserts "had Mother Nature been a real parent, she would have been in jail for child abuse and murder"JOURNAL, Bostrom, Nick, June 2005, IN DEFENSE OF POSTHUMAN DIGNITY, Bioethics, 19, 3, 202–214, 10.1111/j.1467-8519.2005.00437.x, 0269-9702, thus not worthy of unqualified protection.Similarly, Arthur Caplan opposes naturalistic objections to life extension enhancements, by claiming that:"The explanation of why ageing occurs has many of the attributes of a stochastic or chance phenomenon. And this makes ageing unnatural and in no way an intrinsic part of human nature. As such, there is no reason why it is intrinsically wrong to try to reverse or cure ageing."JOURNAL, Caplan, Arthur L., 2005-07-01, Death as an unnatural process: Why is it wrong to seek a cure for ageing?, EMBO Reports, 6, S1, S72–S75, 10.1038/sj.embor.7400435, 1469-221X, 15995668, 1369280,

See also

{{div col|colwidth=18em}} {{div col end}}

References

{{Reflist|30em}}


- content above as imported from Wikipedia
- "human nature" does not exist on GetWiki (yet)
- time: 1:09pm EDT - Fri, May 24 2019
[ this remote article is provided by Wikipedia ]
LATEST EDITS [ see all ]
GETWIKI 09 MAY 2016
GETWIKI 18 OCT 2015
M.R.M. Parrott
Biographies
GETWIKI 20 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 19 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 18 AUG 2014
Wikinfo
Culture
CONNECT