SUPPORT THE WORK

GetWiki

fallacy

ARTICLE SUBJECTS
aesthetics  →
being  →
complexity  →
database  →
enterprise  →
ethics  →
fiction  →
history  →
internet  →
knowledge  →
language  →
licensing  →
linux  →
logic  →
method  →
news  →
perception  →
philosophy  →
policy  →
purpose  →
religion  →
science  →
sociology  →
software  →
truth  →
unix  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE TYPES
essay  →
feed  →
help  →
system  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE ORIGINS
critical  →
discussion  →
forked  →
imported  →
original  →
fallacy
[ temporary import ]
please note:
- the content below is remote from Wikipedia
- it has been imported raw for GetWiki
A fallacy is the use of invalid or otherwise faulty reasoning, or "wrong moves"BOOK, Fallacies and Judgments of Reasonablene Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma-Dialectical Discussion Rules, van Eemeren, Frans, Garssen, Bart, Meuffels, Bert, 2009, Springer, 978-90-481-2613-2, Dordrecht, 10.1007/978-90-481-2614-9, in the construction of an argument.{{aut|Harry J. Gensler}}, The A to Z of Logic (2010:p74). Rowman & Littlefield, {{ISBN|9780810875968}}BOOK, The Death of Argument, Woods, John, 9789048167005, Applied Logic Series, 32, 2004, 3–23, John Woods (logician), 10.1007/978-1-4020-2712-3_1, Who Cares About the Fallacies?, A fallacious argument may be deceptive by appearing to be better than it really is. Some fallacies are committed intentionally to manipulate or persuade by deception, while others are committed unintentionally due to carelessness or ignorance. The soundness of legal arguments depends on the context in which the arguments are made.BOOK, Bustamente, Thomas, Dahlman, Christian, Argument types and fallacies in legal argumentation, 2015, Springer International Publishing, Heidelberg, 978-3-319-16147-1, x, Fallacies are commonly divided into "formal" and "informal". A formal fallacy can be expressed neatly in a standard system of logic, such as propositional logic, while an informal fallacy originates in an error in reasoning other than an improper logical form.WEB,weblink Informal Fallacies, Northern Kentucky University, 2013-09-10, Arguments containing informal fallacies may be formally valid, but still fallacious.WEB, Dowden, Bradley, Fallacy,weblink Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 17 February 2016, A special case is a mathematical fallacy, an intentionally invalid mathematical proof, often with the error subtle and somehow concealed. Mathematical fallacies are typically crafted and exhibited for educational purposes, usually taking the form of spurious proofs of obvious contradictions.

Overview

Fallacies are defects that weaken arguments. Fallacious arguments are very common and can be persuasive in common use. They may be even "unsubstantiated assertions that are often delivered with a conviction that makes them sound as though they are proven facts".BOOK, The new handbook of cognitive therapy techniques, McMullin, Rian E., 2000, W. W. Norton, 978-0393703139, [Rev. ed.], New York, 41580357, Informal fallacies in particular are found frequently in mass media such as television and newspapers.JOURNAL, McMurtry, John, The mass media: An analysis of their system of fallacy, Interchange, December 1990, 21, 4, 49–66, 10.1007/BF01810092, It is important to understand what fallacies are so that one can recognize them in either one's own or others' writing. Avoiding fallacies will strengthen one's ability to produce strong arguments.It can be difficult to evaluate whether an argument is fallacious, as arguments exist along a continuum of soundness and an argument that has several stages or parts might have some sound sections and some fallacious ones.WEB, DeLancey, Craig, Ph.D., Evaluating Arguments—Distinguishing between reasonable and fallacious tactics,weblink oswego.edu, self-published, 7 March 2018,weblink" title="web.archive.org/web/20130903171329weblink">weblink 2013-09-03, yes, "Fallacious arguments usually have the deceptive appearance of being good arguments."{{refn|1={{named ref|name=Damer 2009}} page 52.}} Recognizing fallacies in everyday arguments may be difficult since arguments are often embedded in rhetorical patterns that obscure the logical connections between statements. Informal fallacies may also exploit the emotional, intellectual, or psychological weaknesses of the audience. Recognizing fallacies can develop reasoning skills to expose the weaker links between premises and conclusions to better discern between what appears to be true and what is true.Argumentation theory provides a different approach to understanding and classifying fallacies. In this approach, an argument is regarded as an interactive protocol between individuals that attempts to resolve their disagreements. The protocol is regulated by certain rules of interaction, so violations of these rules are fallacies.Fallacies are used in place of valid reasoning to communicate a point with the intention to persuade. Examples in the mass media today include but are not limited to propaganda, advertisements, politics, newspaper editorials and opinion-based “news” shows.

Systems of classification

Because of their variety of structure and application, fallacies are challenging to classify so as to satisfy all practitioners. Fallacies can be classified strictly by either their structure or their content, such as classifying them as formal fallacies or informal fallacies, respectively. The classification of informal fallacies may be subdivided into categories such as linguistic, relevance through omission, relevance through intrusion, and relevance through presumption.BOOK, Pirie, Madsen, Madsen Pirie, How to Win Every Argument: The Use and Abuse of Logic,weblink 10 September 2015, 2006, A&C Black, 978-0-8264-9006-3, 46, On the other hand, fallacies may be classified by the process by which they occur, such as material fallacies (content), verbal fallacies (linguistic), and again formal fallacies (error in inference). In turn, material fallacies may be placed into the more general category of informal fallacies. Yet, verbal fallacies may be placed in either formal or informal classifications; compare equivocation which is a word or phrase based ambiguity, e. g. "he is mad", which may refer to either him being angry or clinically insane, to the fallacy of composition which is premise and inference based ambiguity, e. g. "this must be a good basketball team because each of its members is an outstanding player".WEB, fallacy,weblink Encyclopedia Brittanica, Encyclopedia Brittanica, 13 June 2017, Even the definitions of the classes may not be unique. For example, Whately treats material fallacies as a complement to logical fallacies, which makes them synonymous to informal fallacies, while others consider them to be a subclass of informal fallacies, like mentioned above.

Aristotle

Aristotle was the first to systematize logical errors into a list, as being able to refute an opponent's thesis is one way of winning an argument.BOOK, Frans, van Eemeren, Bart, Garssen, Bert, Meuffels, Fallacies and judgements of reasonableness, Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma-Dialectical Discussion Rules, 2009, Springer Science+Business Media B.V., Dordrecht, 978-90-481-2613-2, 2, English, 1, Aristotle's "Sophistical Refutations" (De Sophisticis Elenchis) identifies thirteen fallacies. He divided them up into two major types, linguistic fallacies and non-linguistic fallacies, some depending on language and others that do not depend on language.WEB,weblink Aristotle's original 13 fallacies, The Non Sequitur, 2013-05-28, 2008-03-13, WEB,weblink Aristotle's 13 fallacies, www.logiclaw.co.uk, 2017-12-12, These fallacies are called verbal fallacies and material fallacies, respectively. A material fallacy is an error in what the arguer is talking about, while a verbal fallacy is an error in how the arguer is talking. Verbal fallacies are those in which a conclusion is obtained by improper or ambiguous use of words.WEB,weblinkweblink" title="web.archive.org/web/20080905215503weblink">weblink yes, 2008-09-05, PHIL 495: Philosophical Writing (Spring 2008), Texas A&M University, 2013-09-10, An example of a language dependent fallacy is given as a debate as to who amongst humanity are learners: the wise or the ignorant.BOOK, Frans, van Eemeren, Bart, Garssen, Bert, Meuffels, Fallacies and judgements of reasonableness, Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma-Dialectical Discussion Rules, 2009, Springer Science+Business Media B.V., Dordrecht, 978-90-481-2613-2, 3, English, 1, A language-independent fallacy is for example:
  1. "Coriscus is different from Socrates."
  2. "Socrates is a man."
  3. "Therefore, Coriscus is different from a man."BOOK, Frans, van Eemeren, Bart, Garssen, Bert, Meuffels, Fallacies and judgements of reasonableness, Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma-Dialectical Discussion Rules, 2009, Springer Science+Business Media B.V., Dordrecht, 978-90-481-2613-2, 4, English, 1,

Whately's grouping

Richard Whately defines a fallacy broadly as, "any argument, or apparent argument, which professes to be decisive of the matter at hand, while in reality it is not".Frans H. van Eemeren, Bart Garssen, Bert Meuffels (2009). Fallacies and Judgments of Reasonableness: Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma-Dialectical Discussion Rules, p.8. {{ISBN|9789048126149}}.Whately divided fallacies into two groups: logical and material. According to Whately, logical fallacies are arguments where the conclusion does not follow from the premises. Material fallacies are not logical errors because the conclusion does follow from the premises. He then divided the logical group into two groups: purely logical and semi-logical. The semi-logical group included all of Aristotle's sophisms except:ignoratio elenchi, petitio principii, and non causa pro causa, which are in the material group.BOOK, P., Coffey, 1912, The Science of Logic, Longmans, Green, and Company, 12018756,weblink 302, 2016-02-22,

Other systems of classification

Of other classifications of fallacies in general the most famous are those of Francis Bacon and J. S. Mill. Bacon (Novum Organum, Aph. 33, 38 sqq.) divided fallacies into four Idola (Idols, i.e. False Appearances), which summarize the various kinds of mistakes to which the human intellect is prone. With these should be compared the Offendicula of Roger Bacon, contained in the Opus maius, pt. i. J. S. Mill discussed the subject in book v. of his Logic, and Jeremy Bentham's Book of Fallacies (1824) contains valuable remarks. See Rd. Whateley's Logic, bk. v.; A. de Morgan, Formal Logic (1847); A. Sidgwick, Fallacies (1883) and other textbooks.

Formal fallacy

A formal fallacy, deductive fallacy, logical fallacy or non sequitur (Latin for "it does not follow") is a flaw in the structure of a deductive argument which renders the argument invalid. The flaw can neatly be expressed in standard system of logic. Such an argument is always considered to be wrong.The presence of the formal fallacy does not imply anything about the argument's premises or its conclusion. Both may actually be true, or may even be more probable as a result of the argument; but the deductive argument is still invalid because the conclusion does not follow from the premises in the manner described.{{Dubious span|text=By extension, an argument can contain a formal fallacy even if the argument is not a deductive one: for instance, an inductive argument that incorrectly applies principles of probability or causality can be said to commit a formal fallacy.|date=May 2018}} "Since deductive arguments depend on formal properties and inductive arguments don't, formal fallacies apply only to deductive arguments."A logical form such as "A and B" is independent of any particular conjunction of meaningful propositions. Logical form alone can guarantee that given true premises, a true conclusion must follow. However, formal logic makes no such guarantee if any premise is false; the conclusion can be either true or false. Any formal error or logical fallacy similarly invalidates the deductive guarantee. Both the argument and all its premises must be true for a statement to be true.The term logical fallacy is in a sense self-contradictory, because logic refers to valid reasoning, whereas a fallacy is the use of poor reasoning. Therefore, the term formal fallacy is preferred. In informal discourse however, logical fallacy is used to mean an argument which is problematic for any reason.The term non sequitur denotes a general formal fallacy, often meaning one which does not belong to any named subclass of formal fallacies like affirming the consequent.

Common examples

Ecological fallacy

An ecological fallacy is committed when one draws an inference from data based on the premise that qualities observed for groups necessarily hold for individuals; for example, "if countries with more Protestants tend to have higher suicide rates, then Protestants must be more likely to commit suicide."BOOK, Freedman, David A., Encyclopedia of Social Science Research Methods, 2004, Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA, 978-0761923633, 293–295, Ecological Fallacy, Michael S. Lewis-Beck & Alan Bryman & Tim Futing Liao,

The fallacy fork

Maarten Boudry argues that formal, deductive fallacies rarely occur in real life and that arguments that would be fallacious in formally deductive terms are not necessarily so when context and prior probabilities are taken into account, thus making the argument defeasible and inductive. For a given fallacy, one must either characterize it by means of a deductive argumentation schema, which rarely applies (the first prong of the fork) or one must relax definitions and add nuance to take the actual intent and context of the argument into account (the other prong of the fork). To argue, for example, that one became nauseous after eating a mushroom because the mushroom was poisonous could be an example of the post hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy unless one were actually arguing inductively and probabilistically that it is likely that the mushroom caused the illness since some mushrooms are poisonous, it is possible to misidentify a mushroom as edible, one doesn't usually feel nauseous, etc.JOURNAL, Boudry, Maarten, Maarten Boudry, The Fallacy Fork: Why It's Time to Get Rid of Fallacy Theory, Skeptical Inquirer, 2017, 41, 5, 46–51,

Informal fallacy

In contrast to a formal fallacy, an informal fallacy originates in a reasoning error other than a flaw in the logical form of the argument. A deductive argument containing an informal fallacy may be formally valid, but still remain rationally unpersuasive. Nevertheless, informal fallacies apply to both deductive and non-deductive arguments.Though the form of the argument may be relevant, fallacies of this type are the "types of mistakes in reasoning that arise from the mishandling of the content of the propositions constituting the argument".BOOK, Copi, Irving M., Cohen, Carl, 2005, Introduction to Logic, 12, Pearson Education, Inc., 978-0-13-189834-9, p.125

Faulty generalization

A special subclass of the informal fallacies is the set of faulty generalizations, also known as inductive fallacies. Here the most important issue concerns inductive strength or methodology (for example, statistical inference). In the absence of sufficient evidence, drawing conclusions based on induction is unwarranted and fallacious. With the backing of empirical evidence, however, the conclusions may become warranted and convincing (at which point the arguments are no longer considered fallacious).{{citation needed|date=February 2016}}

Hasty generalization

For instance, hasty generalization is making assumptions about a whole group or range of cases based on a sample that is inadequate (usually because it is atypical or just too small).Stereotypes about people ("frat boys are drunkards", "grad students are nerdy", "women don’t enjoy sports", etc.) are a common example of the principle.Hasty generalisation often follows a pattern such as:
X is true for A. X is true for B. Therefore, X is true for C, D, etc.
While never a valid logical deduction, if such an inference can be made on statistical grounds, it may nonetheless be convincing. This is because with enough empirical evidence, the generalization is no longer a hasty one.

Relevance fallacy

The fallacies of relevance are a broad class of informal fallacies (see the navbox below), generically represented by missing the point: Presenting an argument, which may be sound, but fails to address the issue in question.

Argumentum ex silentio

An argument from silence features an unwarranted conclusion advanced based on the absence of data.

Examples of informal fallacies

Post hoc (false cause)

This fallacy gets its name from the Latin phrase "post hoc, ergo propter hoc," which translates as "after this, therefore because of this."Definition: Assuming that because B comes after A, A caused B.Sometimes one event really does cause another one that comes later—for example, if I register for a class, and my name later appears on the roll, it's true that the first event caused the one that came later. But sometimes two events that seem related in time aren't really related as cause and event. That is, correlation isn't the same thing as causation.

Slippery slope

Definition: The arguer claims that a sort of chain reaction, usually ending in some dire consequence, will take place, but in fact there is not enough evidence for that assumption.The arguer asserts that if we take even one step onto the "slippery slope," we will end up sliding all the way to the bottom; he or she assumes we can't stop halfway down the hill.WEB,weblink The Most Common Logical Fallacies, www.webpages.uidaho.edu, 2017-12-12,

False analogy

This error in reasoning occurs when claims are supported by unsound comparisons, hence the false analogy's informal nickname of the "apples and oranges" fallacy.JOURNAL, Kornprobst, Markus, Comparing Apples and Oranges? Leading and Misleading Uses of Historical Analogies, Millennium â€” Journal of International Studies, 2007, 36, 29–49, 10.1177/03058298070360010301,weblinkweblink" title="archive.is/20131030094151weblink">weblink yes, 30 October 2013, 29 October 2013,

Measurement fallacy

Some of the fallacies described above may be committed in the context of measurement.Where mathematical fallacies are subtle mistakes in reasoning leading to invalid mathematical proofs, measurement fallacies are unwarranted inferential leaps involved in the extrapolation of raw data to a measurement-based value claim. The ancient Greek Sophist Protagoras was one of the first thinkers to propose that humans can generate reliable measurements through his "human-measure" principle and the practice of dissoi logoi (arguing multiple sides of an issue).BOOK, Schiappa, Edward, Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric, 1991, University of South Carolina Press, Columbia, SC, 978-0872497580, BOOK, Protagoras, The Older Sophists, 1972, Hackett Publishing Co., Indianapolis, IN, 978-0872205567, This history helps explain why measurement fallacies are informed by informal logic and argumentation theory.

Knowledge value measurement fallacy

Increasing availability and circulation of big data are driving proliferation of new metrics for scholarly authority,JOURNAL, Meho, Lokman I., 2007, The Rise and Rise of Citation Analysis, Physics World, January, 32–36, physics/0701012, 2007physics...1012M, NEWS,weblink The New Metrics of Scholarly Authority, Jensen, Michael, June 15, 2007, The Chronicle of Higher Education, 28 October 2013, The Chron, Riley, Michael G., 0009-5982, 1554535, and there is lively discussion regarding the relative usefulness of such metrics for measuring the value of knowledge production in the context of an "information tsunami".JOURNAL, Baveye, Phillippe C., 2010, Sticker Shock and Looming Tsunami: The High Cost of Academic Serials in Perspective,weblink Journal of Scholarly Publishing, 41, 2, 191–215, 10.1353/scp.0.0074, For example, anchoring fallacies can occur when unwarranted weight is given to data generated by metrics that the arguers themselves acknowledge is flawed. For example, limitations of the journal impact factor (JIF) are well documented,BOOK,weblink Impact Factors, Journal Quality, and Communication Journals: A Report for the Council of Communication Associations, National Communication Journal, National Communication Association, 2013, Washington, D.C., 2016-02-22, April 4, 2016,weblink" title="web.archive.org/web/20160404212454weblink">weblink yes, and even JIF pioneer Eugene Garfield notes, "while citation data create new tools for analyses of research performance, it should be stressed that they supplement rather than replace other quantitative-and qualitative-indicators."JOURNAL, Gafield, Eugene, What Citations Tell us About Canadian Research, Canadian Journal of Library and Information Science, 1993, 18, 4, 34, To the extent that arguers jettison acknowledged limitations of JIF-generated data in evaluative judgments, or leave behind Garfield's "supplement rather than replace" caveat, they court commission of anchoring fallacies.A naturalistic fallacy can occur for example in the case of sheer quantity metrics based on the premise "more is better" or, in the case of developmental assessment in the field of psychology, "higher is better."JOURNAL, Stein, Zachary, Myth Busting and Metric Making: Refashioning the Discourse about Development, Integral Leadership Review, October 2008, 8, 5,weblinkweblink" title="archive.is/20131030094158weblink">weblink October 30, 2013, October 28, 2013, A false analogy occurs when claims are supported by unsound comparisons between data points. For example, the Scopus and Web of Science bibliographic databases have difficulty distinguishing between citations of scholarly work that are arms-length endorsements, ceremonial citations, or negative citations (indicating the citing author withholds endorsement of the cited work). Hence, measurement-based value claims premised on the uniform quality of all citations may be questioned on false analogy grounds.For the next example let us consider Academic Analytics' Faculty Scholarly Productivity Index, which purports to measure overall faculty productivity, yet the tool does not capture data based on citations in books. This creates a possibility that low productivity measurements using the tool may constitute argument from silence fallacies, to the extent that such measurements are supported by the absence of book citation data.Ecological fallacies can be committed when one measures scholarly productivity of a sub-group of individuals (e.g. "Puerto Rican" faculty) via reference to aggregate data about a larger and different group (e.g. "Hispanic" faculty).JOURNAL, Allen, Henry L., Faculty Workload and Productivity: Ethnic and Gender Disparities, NEA 1997 Almanac of Higher Education, 1997, 39,weblink PDF, October 29, 2013,

Intentional fallacy

Sometimes a speaker or writer uses a fallacy intentionally. In any context, including academic debate, a conversation among friends, political discourse, advertising, or for comedic purposes, the arguer may use fallacious reasoning to try to persuade the listener or reader, by means other than offering relevant evidence, that the conclusion is true.Examples of this include the speaker or writer:BOOK,weblink Applications of Grammar: Principles of Effective Communication, Shewan, Edward, Christian Liberty Press, 2003, 978-1-930367-28-9, 2nd, February 22, 2016,weblink Soundness of Argument,
  1. Diverting the argument to unrelated issues with a red herring (Ignoratio elenchi)
  2. Insulting someone's character (argumentum ad hominem)
  3. Assume the conclusion of an argument, a kind of circular reasoning, also called "begging the question" (petitio principi)
  4. Making jumps in logic (non-sequitur)
  5. Identifying a false cause and effect (post hoc ergo propter hoc)
  6. Asserting that everyone agrees (argumentum ad populum, bandwagoning)
  7. Creating a "false dilemma" ("either-or fallacy") in which the situation is oversimplified
  8. Selectively using facts (card-stacking)
  9. Making false or misleading comparisons (false equivalence and false analogy)
  10. Generalizing quickly and sloppily (hasty generalization)
In humor, errors of reasoning are used for comical purposes. Groucho Marx used fallacies of amphiboly, for instance, to make ironic statements; Gary Larson and Scott Adams employed fallacious reasoning in many of their cartoons. Wes Boyer and Samuel Stoddard have written a humorous essay teaching students how to be persuasive by means of a whole host of informal and formal fallacies.WEB,weblink How to Be Persuasive, Boyer, Web, Stoddard, Samuel, Rink Works, December 5, 2012,

Assessment â€” pragmatic theory

According to the pragmatic theory,BOOK, Douglas N., Walton,weblink A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy, University of Alabama Press, Douglas N. Walton, 1995, Tuscaloosa, 324, 9780817307981, a fallacy can in some instances be an error a fallacy, use of a heuristic (short version of an argumentation scheme) to jump to a conclusion. However, even more worryingly, in other instances it is a tactic or ploy used inappropriately in argumentation to try to get the best of a speech part unfairly. There are always two parties to an argument containing a fallacy â€” the perpetrator and the intended victim. The dialogue framework required to support the pragmatic theory of fallacy is built on the presumption that argumentative dialogue has both an adversarial component and a collaborative component. A dialogue has individual goals for each participant, but also collective (shared) goals that apply to all participants. A fallacy of the second kind is seen as more than simply violation of a rule of reasonable dialogue. It is also a deceptive tactic of argumentation, based on sleight-of-hand. Aristotle explicitly compared contentious reasoning to unfair fighting in athletic contest. But the roots of the pragmatic theory go back even further in history to the Sophists. The pragmatic theory finds its roots in the Aristotelian conception of a fallacy as a sophistical refutation, but also supports the view that many of the types of arguments traditionally labelled as fallacies are in fact reasonable techniques of argumentation that can be used, in many cases, to support legitimate goals of dialogue. Hence on the pragmatic approach, each case needs to analyzed individually, to determine by the textual evidence whether the argument is fallacious or reasonable.

See also

{hide}columns-list|colwidth=22em|Lists Concepts Works
  • Attacking Faulty Reasoning{{citation |first = T. Edward |last = Damer |authorlink = T. Edward Damer |author2 = Rudinow, J. |author3 = Barry, V. E. |author4 = Munson, R. |author5 = Black, A. |author6 = Salmon, M. H. |author7 = Cederblom, J. |author8 = Paulsen, D. |author9 = Epstein, R. L. | author10 = Kernberger, C. |author11 = others |title = Attacking Faulty Reasoning: A Practical Guide to Fallacy-free Arguments |edition = 6th |publisher = Wadsworth |place = Belmont, California |isbn = 978-0-495-09506-4 |url =weblink |year = 2009 |accessdate = 2016-02-24 |postscript = . See also Wikipedia article on the book }}
  • Straight and Crooked Thinking
  • Why I Do Not Attend Case Conferences
}}

References

{{Reflist|30em}}

Further reading

  • C. L. Hamblin, Fallacies, Methuen London, 1970. reprinted by Vale Press in 1998 as {{ISBN|0-916475-24-7}}.
  • BOOK, Hans V. Hansen, Robert C. Pinto, Fallacies: classical and contemporary readings, 1995, Penn State Press, 978-0-271-01417-3,
  • BOOK, Frans van Eemeren, Bart Garssen, Bert Meuffels, Fallacies and Judgments of Reasonableness: Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma-Dialectical Discussion, 2009, Springer, 978-90-481-2613-2,
  • Douglas N. Walton, Informal logic: A handbook for critical argumentation. Cambridge University Press, 1989.
  • BOOK, Douglas, Walton, Informal Fallacies, 1987, John Benjamins, Amsterdam,
  • BOOK, Walton, Douglas, A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy, 1995, University of Alabama Press, Tuscaloosa,
  • JOURNAL, Walton, Douglas, Why Fallacies Appear to Be Better Arguments than They Are, Informal Logic, 2010, 30, 2, 159–184,
  • BOOK, John Woods (logician), John Woods, The death of argument: fallacies in agent based reasoning, 2004, Springer, 978-1-4020-2663-8,
  • Fearnside, W. Ward and William B. Holther, Fallacy: The Counterfeit of Argument, 1959.
  • Vincent F. Hendricks, Thought 2 Talk: A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression, New York: Automatic Press / VIP, 2005, {{ISBN|87-991013-7-8}}
  • D. H. Fischer, Historians' Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought, Harper Torchbooks, 1970.
  • Warburton Nigel, Thinking from A to Z, Routledge 1998.
  • Sagan, Carl, "(The Demon-Haunted World|The Demon-Haunted World: Science As a Candle in the Dark)". Ballantine Books, March 1997 {{ISBN|0-345-40946-9}}, 480 pgs. 1996 hardback edition: Random House, {{ISBN|0-394-53512-X}}, xv+457 pages plus addenda insert (some printings). Ch.12.

Historical texts

External links

{{Wiktionary|fallacy}}{{Wikiversity|Recognizing Fallacies}} {{Disinformation}}{{Philosophical logic}}{{Formal Fallacy}}{{Informal Fallacy}}{{Relevance fallacies}}

- content above as imported from Wikipedia
- "fallacy" does not exist on GetWiki (yet)
- time: 3:55am EST - Tue, Dec 11 2018
[ this remote article is provided by Wikipedia ]
LATEST EDITS [ see all ]
GETWIKI 09 MAY 2016
GETWIKI 18 OCT 2015
M.R.M. Parrott
Biographies
GETWIKI 20 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 19 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 18 AUG 2014
Wikinfo
Culture
CONNECT