SUPPORT THE WORK

GetWiki

Jeremy Bentham

ARTICLE SUBJECTS
aesthetics  →
being  →
complexity  →
database  →
enterprise  →
ethics  →
fiction  →
history  →
internet  →
knowledge  →
language  →
licensing  →
linux  →
logic  →
method  →
news  →
perception  →
philosophy  →
policy  →
purpose  →
religion  →
science  →
sociology  →
software  →
truth  →
unix  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE TYPES
essay  →
feed  →
help  →
system  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE ORIGINS
critical  →
discussion  →
forked  →
imported  →
original  →
Jeremy Bentham
[ temporary import ]
please note:
- the content below is remote from Wikipedia
- it has been imported raw for GetWiki
{{short description|British philosopher, jurist, and social reformer}}{{Use British English|date=August 2011}}{{Use dmy dates|date=June 2018}}







factoids

| birth_place = London, England, Kingdom of Great Britain
| death_date = {{Death date and age|df=yes|1832|6|6|1748|2|15}}
| death_place = London, England, United Kingdom
| education = The Queen's College, Oxford (BA 1763; MA 1766)
| school_tradition = Utilitarianism, legal positivism, liberalism
| main_interests = Political philosophy, philosophy of law, ethics, economics
| influences = {{hlist|Protagoras| Epicurus| John Locke| David Hume| Montesquieu| Helvétius| Hobbes| Beccaria|Adam Smith}}
| influenced = {{hlist|John Stuart Mill| Thomas Hodgskin| William Thompson| Henry Sidgwick| Michel Foucault| Peter Singer| John Austin| Robert Owen| H. L. A. Hart | Francis Y. Edgeworth| A. V. Dicey{{sfn|Follett|2000|p=7}}| Étienne Dumont}}
| notable_ideas = Greatest happiness principle
| signature = Jeremy Bentham signature.svg
}}Jeremy Bentham ({{IPAc-en|ˈ|b|ɛ|n|θ|ə|m}}; 15 February 1748 O.S. 4 February 1747] – 6 June 1832) was an English philosopher, jurist, and social reformer regarded as the founder of modern utilitarianism.Bentham defined as the "fundamental axiom" of his philosophy the principle that "it is the greatest happiness of the greatest number that is the measure of right and wrong."{{sfn|Bentham|1977|p=393}}{{sfn|Burns|2005 |pp=46–61 }} He became a leading theorist in Anglo-American philosophy of law, and a political radical whose ideas influenced the development of welfarism. He advocated for individual and economic freedoms, the separation of church and state, freedom of expression, equal rights for women, the right to divorce, and the decriminalising of homosexual acts.{{sfn|Bentham|2008|pp=389–406}}{{sfn|Campos Boralevi|2012|p=37}} He called for the abolition of slavery, of the death penalty, and of physical punishment, including that of children.{{sfn|Bedau|1983|pp=1033-1065}} He has also become known as an early advocate of animal rights.{{sfn|Sunstein|2004|pp=3-4}}{{sfn|Francione|2004|p=139|ps=: footnote 78}}{{sfn|Gruen|2003|p=}}{{sfn|Benthall|2007|p=1}} Though strongly in favour of the extension of individual legal rights, he opposed the idea of natural law and natural rights (both of which are considered "divine" or "God-given" in origin), calling them "nonsense upon stilts".{{sfn|Harrison|1995|pp=85-88}} Bentham was also a sharp critic of legal fictions.Bentham's students included his secretary and collaborator James Mill, the latter's son, John Stuart Mill, the legal philosopher John Austin, as well as Robert Owen, one of the founders of utopian socialism. He "had considerable influence on the reform of prisons, schools, poor laws, law courts, and Parliament itself."{{sfn|Roberts|Roberts|Bisson|2016|p=307}}On his death in 1832, Bentham left instructions for his body to be first dissected, and then to be permanently preserved as an "auto-icon" (or self-image), which would be his memorial. This was done, and the auto-icon is now on public display at University College London (UCL). Because of his arguments in favour of the general availability of education, he has been described as the "spiritual founder" of UCL. However, he played only a limited direct part in its foundation.

Biography

Early life

File:Jeremy Bentham by Thomas Frye.jpg|thumb|Portrait of Bentham by the studio of Thomas FryeThomas FryeBentham was born on the 15 February 1748 in Houndsditch, London, to a wealthy family that supported the Tory party. He was reportedly a child prodigy: he was found as a toddler sitting at his father's desk reading a multi-volume history of England, and he began to study Latin at the age of three. He learnt to play the violin and at the age of seven, Bentham would perform sonatas by Handel during dinner parties.{{sfn|Warren|1969|p=}} He had one surviving sibling, Samuel Bentham, with whom he was close.He attended Westminster School and, in 1760, at age 12, was sent by his father to The Queen's College, Oxford, where he completed his bachelor's degree in 1763 and his master's degree in 1766. He trained as a lawyer and, though he never practised, was called to the bar in 1769. He became deeply frustrated with the complexity of the English legal code, which he termed the "Demon of Chicane".{{citation needed||date=April 2019}} When the American colonies published their Declaration of Independence in July 1776, the British government did not issue any official response but instead secretly commissioned London lawyer and pamphleteer John Lind to publish a rebuttal.{{sfn|Dupont |Onuf|2008|pp=32–33}} His 130-page tract was distributed in the colonies and contained an essay titled "Short Review of the Declaration" written by Bentham, a friend of Lind, which attacked and mocked the Americans' political philosophy.{{sfn|Armitage|2007|p=}}{{sfn|Anonymous|1776|p=3}}

Abortive prison project

In 1786 and 1787, Bentham travelled to Krichev in White Russia (modern Belarus) to visit his brother, Samuel, who was engaged in managing various industrial and other projects for Prince Potemkin. It was Samuel (as Jeremy later repeatedly acknowledged) who conceived the basic idea of a circular building at the hub of a larger compound as a means of allowing a small number of managers to oversee the activities of a large and unskilled workforce.{{Sfn | Semple | 1993 | pp = 99–100}}{{citation |title= Prisons and prison systems: a global encyclopedia| first = Mitchel P | last = Roth |year= 2006 |publisher=Greenwood |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=RTH31DgbTzgC&pg=PA33|page= 33| isbn = 9780313328565 }}Bentham began to develop this model, particularly as applicable to prisons, and outlined his ideas in a series of letters sent home to his father in England.{{Sfn | Semple | 1993 | pp = 99–101}} He supplemented the supervisory principle with the idea of contract management; that is, an administration by contract as opposed to trust, where the director would have a pecuniary interest in lowering the average rate of mortality.{{Sfn | Semple | 1993 | pp = 134–40}} The Panopticon was intended to be cheaper than the prisons of his time, as it required fewer staff; "Allow me to construct a prison on this model," Bentham requested to a Committee for the Reform of Criminal Law, "I will be the gaoler. You will see ... that the gaoler will have no salary—will cost nothing to the nation." As the watchmen cannot be seen, they need not be on duty at all times, effectively leaving the watching to the watched. According to Bentham's design, the prisoners would also be used as menial labour, walking on wheels to spin looms or run a water wheel. This would decrease the cost of the prison and give a possible source of income.{{Sfn | Bentham | 1995 | pages = 29–95}}The ultimately abortive proposal for a panopticon prison to be built in England was one among his many proposals for legal and social reform.{{sfn|Bentham|1787|p=}} But Bentham spent some sixteen years of his life developing and refining his ideas for the building and hoped that the government would adopt the plan for a National Penitentiary appointing him as contractor-governor. Although the prison was never built, the concept had an important influence on later generations of thinkers. Twentieth-century French philosopher Michel Foucault argued that the panopticon was paradigmatic of several 19th-century "disciplinary" institutions.{{sfn|Foucault|1977|pp=200, 249–256}} Bentham remained bitter throughout his later life about the rejection of the panopticon scheme, convinced that it had been thwarted by the King and an aristocratic elite. It was largely because of his sense of injustice and frustration that he developed his ideas of "sinister interest"—that is, of the vested interests of the powerful conspiring against a wider public interest—which underpinned many of his broader arguments for reform.BOOK, Philip, Schofield, Bentham: a guide for the perplexed, 2009, London, Continuum, 978-0-8264-9589-1, 90–93, File:Panopticon.jpg|thumb|Elevation, section and plan of Bentham's panopticon prison, drawn by Willey ReveleyWilley ReveleyOn his return to England from Russia, Bentham had commissioned drawings from an architect, Willey Reveley.{{Sfn | Semple | 1993 | p = 118}} In 1791, he published the material he had written as a book, although he continued to refine his proposals for many years to come. He had by now decided that he wanted to see the prison built: when finished, it would be managed by himself as contractor-governor, with the assistance of Samuel. After unsuccessful attempts to interest the authorities in Ireland and revolutionary France,Semple 1993, pp. 102–4, 107–8. he started trying to persuade the prime minister, William Pitt, to revive an earlier abandoned scheme for a National Penitentiary in England, this time to be built as a panopticon. He was eventually successful in winning over Pitt and his advisors, and in 1794 was paid £2,000 for preliminary work on the project.Semple 1993, pp. 108–10, 262.The intended site was one that had been authorised (under an act of 1779) for the earlier Penitentiary, at Battersea Rise; but the new proposals ran into technical legal problems and objections from the local landowner, Earl Spencer.Semple 1993, pp. 169–89. Other sites were considered, including one at Hanging Wood, near Woolwich, but all proved unsatisfactory.Semple 1993, pp. 194–7. Eventually Bentham turned to a site at Tothill Fields, near Westminster. Although this was common land, with no landowner, there were a number of parties with interests in it, including Earl Grosvenor, who owned a house on an adjacent site and objected to the idea of a prison overlooking it. Again, therefore, the scheme ground to a halt.Semple 1993, pp. 197–217. At this point, however, it became clear that a nearby site at Millbank, adjoining the Thames, was available for sale, and this time things ran more smoothly. Using government money, Bentham bought the land on behalf of the Crown for £12,000 in November 1799.Semple 1993, pp. 217–22.From his point of view, the site was far from ideal, being marshy, unhealthy, and too small. When he asked the government for more land and more money, however, the response was that he should build only a small-scale experimental prison—which he interpreted as meaning that there was little real commitment to the concept of the panopticon as a cornerstone of penal reform.Semple 1993, pp. 226–31. Negotiations continued, but in 1801 Pitt resigned from office, and in 1803 the new Addington administration decided not to proceed with the project.Semple 1993, pp. 236–9. Bentham was devastated: "They have murdered my best days."Semple 1993, p. 244.Nevertheless, a few years later the government revived the idea of a National Penitentiary, and in 1811 and 1812 returned specifically to the idea of a panopticon.Semple 1993, pp. 265–79. Bentham, now aged 63, was still willing to be governor. However, as it became clear that there was still no real commitment to the proposal, he abandoned hope, and instead turned his attentions to extracting financial compensation for his years of fruitless effort. His initial claim was for the enormous sum of nearly £700,000, but he eventually settled for the more modest (but still considerable) sum of £23,000.Semple 1993, pp. 279–81. An Act of Parliament in 1812 transferred his title in the site to the Crown.Penitentiary House, etc. Act: 52 Geo. III, c. 44 (1812).More successful was his cooperation with Patrick Colquhoun in tackling the corruption in the Pool of London. This resulted in the Thames Police Bill of 1798, which was passed in 1800.{{efn|An Act for the More Effectual Prevention of Depredations on the River Thames (39 & 40 Geo 3 c 87)}} The bill created the Thames River Police, which was the first preventive police force in the country and was a precedent for Robert Peel's reforms 30 years later.{{sfn|Everett|1966|pp=67–69}}

Correspondence and contemporary influences

Bentham was in correspondence with many influential people. In the 1780s, for example, Bentham maintained a correspondence with the aging Adam Smith, in an unsuccessful attempt to convince Smith that interest rates should be allowed to freely float.{{sfn|Persky|2007|p=228}} As a result of his correspondence with Mirabeau and other leaders of the French Revolution, Bentham was declared an honorary citizen of France.{{sfn|Bentham|2002|p=291}} He was an outspoken critic of the revolutionary discourse of natural rights and of the violence that arose after the Jacobins took power (1792). Between 1808 and 1810, he held a personal friendship with Latin American Independence Precursor Francisco de Miranda and paid visits to Miranda's Grafton Way house in London. He also developed links with José Cecilio del Valle.JOURNAL, Darío, Rubén, La Literatura en Centro-América, Revista de artes y letras, 1887, XI, 591,weblink 25 March 2019, Biblioteca Nacional de Chile, es, MC0060418, In Guatemala there was Valle, a man of vast intellect, friend of Jeremías Bentham, with whom he corresponded frequently. Bentham sent him shortly before dying a lock of his hair and a golden ring, shiny as José Cecilio's style., NEWS, Laura Geggel, Oddball Philosopher Had His Mummified Body Put on Display … and Now His Rings Are Missing,weblink 26 March 2019, Live Science, 11 September 2018, "We can safely assume that [Guatemalan philosopher and politician] José del Valle received one, as he is featured wearing it in a portrait," Causer said. "Interestingly, on the bookshelf of that portrait is one of Bentham’s works, as well as a Spanish translation of Say’s 'Traité d’économie politique.' It’s a neat, tangible link between Bentham, Say and del Valle.",

Westminster Review

In 1823, he co-founded The Westminster Review with James Mill as a journal for the "Philosophical Radicals"—a group of younger disciples through whom Bentham exerted considerable influence in British public life.{{sfn|Hamburger|1965|p=}}{{sfn|Thomas|1979|p=}} One was John Bowring, to whom Bentham became devoted, describing their relationship as "son and father": he appointed Bowring political editor of The Westminster Review and eventually his literary executor.{{sfn|Bartle|1963|p=}} Another was Edwin Chadwick, who wrote on hygiene, sanitation and policing and was a major contributor to the Poor Law Amendment Act: Bentham employed Chadwick as a secretary and bequeathed him a large legacy.{{sfn|Everett|1968|p=94}}

Old age

An insight into his character is given in Michael St. John Packe's The Life of John Stuart Mill:
}}
A psychobiographical study by Philip Lucas and Anne Sheeran argues that he may have had Asperger's syndrome.{{sfn|Lucas|Sheeran|2006|pp= 26–27}} Bentham was an atheist.{{sfn|Crimmins|1986|p=95}} {{harvnb|González|2012|p=81}} writes, "In sum, with Hume's agnosticism and Bentham's atheism, the fundamental voluntarist thesis about the gulf between the divine and the human mind reaches new depths, and this serves to reinforce and radicalise the rejection, begun by Pufendorf, of Grotian rights-theory as the appropriate means of formulating the conventionalist theory of the moral life." And {{harvnb|Crimmins|1990|p=283}} notes, "Making allowance for Adams's cautious phrasing, this is a concise statement of Bentham's secular positivism, but it is also important to note the conviction with which Bentham held his atheism."

Death and the auto-icon

(File:"Mortal Remains" of Jeremy Bentham, 1832 Wellcome L0007730.jpg|thumb|left|Bentham's Public dissection)(File:Jeremy Bentham Auto-Icon.jpg|thumb|upright|Bentham's auto-icon)(File:Jeremy Bentham's Severed Head.JPG|thumb|right|Jeremy Bentham's severed head, on temporary display at UCL)Bentham died on 6 June 1832 aged 84 at his residence in Queen Square Place in Westminster, London, England. He had continued to write up to a month before his death, and had made careful preparations for the dissection of his body after death and its preservation as an auto-icon. As early as 1769, when Bentham was 21 years old, he made a will leaving his body for dissection to a family friend, the physician and chemist George Fordyce, whose daughter, Maria Sophia (1765–1858), married Jeremy's brother Samuel Bentham. A paper written in 1830, instructing Thomas Southwood Smith to create the auto-icon, was attached to his last will, dated 30 May 1832.On 8 June 1832, two days after his death, invitations were distributed to a select group of friends, and on the following day at 3 p.m., Southwood Smith delivered a lengthy oration over Bentham's remains in the Webb Street School of Anatomy & Medicine in Southwark, London. The printed oration contains a frontispiece with an engraving of Bentham's body partly covered by a sheet.Afterward, the skeleton and head were preserved and stored in a wooden cabinet called the "Auto-icon", with the skeleton padded out with hay and dressed in Bentham's clothes. Originally kept by his disciple Thomas Southwood Smith, it was acquired by University College London in 1850. It is normally kept on public display at the end of the South Cloisters in the main building of the college; however, for the retirement of Sir Malcolm Grant, it was brought to attend his final council meeting. This was the only time that the body has been taken to a UCL council meeting; there is a persistent myth that he is taken to all meetings. Bentham's body was only taken to that one meeting because of the persistent myth about Bentham's attendance, and the curator at the time, Nick Booth, thought it would be a good idea for Bentham to attend once. This will never happen again, as there is a risk that the beetles in the carpet could contaminate the body and slowly consume it.AV MEDIA
, Das, Subhadra (curator)
, November 19, 2018
, The Boring Talks
, #25 Jeremy Bentham's 'Auto-Icon'
, podcast
, English
,weblink
, BBC
, Bentham had intended the Auto-icon to incorporate his actual head, mummified to resemble its appearance in life. Southwood Smith's experimental efforts at mummification, based on practices of the indigenous people of New Zealand and involving placing the head under an air pump over sulfuric acid and drawing off the fluids, although technically successful, left the head looking distastefully macabre, with dried and darkened skin stretched tautly over the skull. The auto-icon was therefore given a wax head, fitted with some of Bentham's own hair. The real head was displayed in the same case as the auto-icon for many years, but became the target of repeated student pranks. It is now locked away securely.In 2017, plans were announced to re-exhibit the head and at the same time obtain a DNA sample for sequencing with the goal of identifying genetic evidence of autism.In 2018, Jeremy Bentham's auto-icon was on display in New York City at the Metropolitan Museum of Art Breuer location.

Work

Utilitarianism

{{Utilitarianism}}Bentham's ambition in life was to create a "Pannomion", a complete utilitarian code of law. He not only proposed many legal and social reforms, but also expounded an underlying moral principle on which they should be based. This philosophy of utilitarianism took for its "fundamental axiom", it is the greatest happiness of the greatest number that is the measure of right and wrong".{{sfn|Bentham|1776|p= |loc=Preface (2nd para.)}} Bentham claimed to have borrowed this concept from the writings of Joseph Priestley,{{sfn|Bentham |1821 |p=24 }} although the closest that Priestley in fact came to expressing it was in the form "the good and happiness of the members, that is the majority of the members of any state, is the great standard by which every thing relating to that state must finally be determined".{{sfn|Priestley|1771|p=17}}The "greatest happiness principle", or the principle of utility, forms the cornerstone of all Bentham's thought. By "happiness", he understood a predominance of "pleasure" over "pain". He wrote in The Principles of Morals and Legislation:
}}
Bentham was a rare major figure in the history of philosophy to endorse psychological egoism.Bentham was a determined opponent of religion. Crimmins observes: "Between 1809 and 1823 Jeremy Bentham carried out an exhaustive examination of religion with the declared aim of extirpating religious beliefs, even the idea of religion itself, from the minds of men."{{sfn|Crimmins|1986|p=95}}Bentham suggested a procedure for estimating the moral status of any action, which he called the Hedonistic or felicific calculus. Utilitarianism was revised and expanded by Bentham's student John Stuart Mill. Mill sharply criticized Bentham's view of human nature, which failed to recognize conscience as a human motive. Mill considered Bentham's view "to have done and to be doing very serious evil."Mill, John Stuart Early Essays of John Stuart Mill (London, 1897) pp. 401-404 In Mill's hands, "Benthamism" became a major element in the liberal conception of state policy objectives.Bentham's critics have claimed that he undermined the foundation of a free society by rejecting natural rights. Historian Gertrude Himmelfarb wrote "The principle of the greatest happiness of the greatest number was as inimical to the idea of liberty as to the idea of rights."{{sfn|Himmelfarb|1968|p=77}}In his exposition of the felicific calculus, Bentham proposed a classification of 12 pains and 14 pleasures, by which we might test the "happiness factor" of any action.{{sfn|Bentham|1789|loc=Ch, IV}} Nonetheless, it should not be overlooked that Bentham's "hedonistic" theory (a term from J. J. C. Smart), unlike Mill's, is often criticised for lacking a principle of fairness embodied in a conception of justice. In Bentham and the Common Law Tradition, Gerald J. Postema states: "No moral concept suffers more at Bentham's hand than the concept of justice. There is no sustained, mature analysis of the notion..."{{sfn|Postema|1986|p=148}} Thus, some critics{{who|date=January 2013}} object, it would be acceptable to torture one person if this would produce an amount of happiness in other people outweighing the unhappiness of the tortured individual. However, as P. J. Kelly argued in Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: Jeremy Bentham and the Civil Law, Bentham had a theory of justice that prevented such consequences. According to Kelly, for Bentham the law "provides the basic framework of social interaction by delimiting spheres of personal inviolability within which individuals can form and pursue their own conceptions of well-being".{{sfn|Kelly|1990|p=81}} It provides security, a precondition for the formation of expectations. As the hedonic calculus shows "expectation utilities" to be much higher than natural ones, it follows that Bentham does not favour the sacrifice of a few to the benefit of the many. Law professor Alan Dershowitz has quoted Bentham to argue that torture should sometimes be permitted.Bentham's An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation focuses on the principle of utility and how this view of morality ties into legislative practices. His principle of utility regards "good" as that which produces the greatest amount of pleasure and the minimum amount of pain and "evil" as that which produces the most pain without the pleasure. This concept of pleasure and pain is defined by Bentham as physical as well as spiritual. Bentham writes about this principle as it manifests itself within the legislation of a society. He lays down a set of criteria for measuring the extent of pain or pleasure that a certain decision will create.{{citation needed|date=June 2018}}The criteria are divided into the categories of intensity, duration, certainty, proximity, productiveness, purity, and extent. Using these measurements, he reviews the concept of punishment and when it should be used as far as whether a punishment will create more pleasure or more pain for a society. He calls for legislators to determine whether punishment creates an even more evil offence. Instead of suppressing the evil acts, Bentham argues that certain unnecessary laws and punishments could ultimately lead to new and more dangerous vices than those being punished to begin with, and calls upon legislators to measure the pleasures and pains associated with any legislation and to form laws in order to create the greatest good for the greatest number. He argues that the concept of the individual pursuing his or her own happiness cannot be necessarily declared "right", because often these individual pursuits can lead to greater pain and less pleasure for a society as a whole. Therefore, the legislation of a society is vital to maintain the maximum pleasure and the minimum degree of pain for the greatest number of people.{{citation needed|date=June 2018}}

Economics

(File:Bentham - Defence of usury, 1788 - 5231094.tif|thumb|Defence of Usury, 1788){{Hedonism}}Bentham's opinions about monetary economics were completely different from those of David Ricardo; however, they had some similarities to those of Henry Thornton. He focused on monetary expansion as a means of helping to create full employment. He was also aware of the relevance of forced saving, propensity to consume, the saving-investment relationship, and other matters that form the content of modern income and employment analysis. His monetary view was close to the fundamental concepts employed in his model of utilitarian decision making. His work is considered to be an early precursor of modern welfare economics.{{citation needed|date=June 2018}}Bentham stated that pleasures and pains can be ranked according to their value or "dimension" such as intensity, duration, certainty of a pleasure or a pain. He was concerned with maxima and minima of pleasures and pains; and they set a precedent for the future employment of the maximisation principle in the economics of the consumer, the firm and the search for an optimum in welfare economics.{{sfn|Spiegel|1991|pp=341–343}}Bentham advocated "Pauper Management" which involved the creation of a chain of large workhouses.WEB, Tracts on Poor Laws and Pauper Management, Bentham, Jeremy, bev.berkeley.edu, 1843, 27 March 2019,weblink {{sfn|Himmelfarb| 1968| pp= 74-75}}

Law reform

Bentham was the first person to aggressively advocate for the codification of all of the common law into a coherent set of statutes; he was actually the person who coined the verb "to codify" to refer to the process of drafting a legal code.{{sfn|Morriss|1999|p=}} He lobbied hard for the formation of codification commissions in both England and the United States, and went so far as to write to President James Madison in 1811 to volunteer to write a complete legal code for the young country. After he learned more about American law and realised that most of it was state-based, he promptly wrote to the governors of every single state with the same offer.During his lifetime, Bentham's codification efforts were completely unsuccessful. Even today, they have been completely rejected by almost every common law jurisdiction, including England. However, his writings on the subject laid the foundation for the moderately successful codification work of David Dudley Field II in the United States a generation later.{{sfn|Morriss|1999|p=}}

Animal rights

Bentham is widely regarded as one of the earliest proponents of animal rights.{{sfn|Benthall|2007|p=1}} He argued and believed that the ability to suffer, not the ability to reason, should be the benchmark, or what he called the "insuperable line". If reason alone were the criterion by which we judge who ought to have rights, human infants and adults with certain forms of disability might fall short, too.{{sfn|Bentham|1879|p=}} In 1789, alluding to the limited degree of legal protection afforded to slaves in the French West Indies by the Code Noir, he wrote:
}}
Earlier in that paragraph, Bentham makes clear that he accepted that animals could be killed for food, or in defence of human life, provided that the animal was not made to suffer unnecessarily. Bentham did not object to medical experiments on animals, providing that the experiments had in mind a particular goal of benefit to humanity, and had a reasonable chance of achieving that goal. He wrote that otherwise he had a "decided and insuperable objection" to causing pain to animals, in part because of the harmful effects such practices might have on human beings. In a letter to the editor of the Morning Chronicle in March 1825, he wrote:

Gender and sexuality

Bentham{{year needed|date=July 2018}} said that it was the placing of women in a legally inferior position that made him choose, at the age of eleven, the career of a reformist.{{sfn|Williford|1975|p=167}} Bentham spoke for a complete equality between sexes.Bentham{{year needed|date=July 2018}} nevertheless thought women inferior to men regarding such qualities as "strength of intellectual powers" and "firmness of mind".{{sfn|Bentham|1879|p=48}}The essay Offences Against One's Self,{{sfn|Bentham|2008|pp=389–406}} argued for the liberalisation of laws prohibiting homosexual sex.{{sfn|Campos Boralevi,|2012| p= 40}} The essay remained unpublished during his lifetime for fear of offending public morality. It was published for the first time in 1931.{{sfn|Campos Boralevi,|2012| p= 37}} Bentham does not believe homosexual acts to be unnatural, describing them merely as "irregularities of the venereal appetite". The essay chastises the society of the time for making a disproportionate response to what Bentham appears to consider a largely private offence—public displays or forced acts being dealt with rightly by other laws. When the essay was published in the Journal of Homosexuality in 1978, the "Abstract" stated that Bentham's essay was the "first known argument for homosexual law reform in England".{{sfn|Bentham|2008|pp=389–406}}

Privacy

For Bentham, transparency had moral value. For example, journalism puts power-holders under moral scrutiny. However, Bentham wanted such transparency to apply to everyone. This he describes by picturing the world as a gymnasium in which each "gesture, every turn of limb or feature, in those whose motions have a visible impact on the general happiness, will be noticed and marked down".{{sfn|Bentham|1834|p=101}} He considered both surveillance and transparency to be useful ways of generating understanding and improvements for people's lives.

Fictional entities

Bentham distinguished among fictional entities what he called "fabulous entities" like Prince Hamlet or a centaur, from what he termed "fictitious entities", or necessary objects of discourse, similar to Kant's categories,{{sfn|Cutrofello|2014|p=115}} such as nature, custom, or the social contract.{{sfn|Murphy|2014|p=61–62}}

Bentham and University College London

Bentham is widely associated with the foundation in 1826 of London University (the institution that, in 1836, became University College London), though he was 78 years old when the University opened and played only an indirect role in its establishment. His direct involvement was limited to his buying a single £100 share in the new University, making him just one of over a thousand shareholders.{{sfn|Harte|1998|pp= 5–8}}File:Four founders of UCL.JPG|thumb|right|upright|Henry TonksHenry TonksBentham and his ideas can nonetheless be seen as having inspired several of the actual founders of the University. He strongly believed that education should be more widely available, particularly to those who were not wealthy or who did not belong to the established church; in Bentham's time, membership of the Church of England and the capacity to bear considerable expenses were required of students entering the Universities of Oxford and Cambridge. As the University of London was the first in England to admit all, regardless of race, creed or political belief, it was largely consistent with Bentham's vision. There is some evidence that, from the sidelines, he played a "more than passive part" in the planning discussions for the new institution, although it is also apparent that "his interest was greater than his influence".{{sfn|Harte|1998|pp= 5–8}} He failed in his efforts to see his disciple John Bowring appointed professor of English or History, but he did oversee the appointment of another pupil, John Austin, as the first professor of Jurisprudence in 1829.The more direct associations between Bentham and UCL—the College's custody of his Auto-icon (see above) and of the majority of his surviving papers—postdate his death by some years: the papers were donated in 1849, and the Auto-icon in 1850. A large painting by Henry Tonks hanging in UCL's Flaxman Gallery depicts Bentham approving the plans of the new university, but it was executed in 1922 and the scene is entirely imaginary. Since 1959 (when the Bentham Committee was first established) UCL has hosted the Bentham Project, which is progressively publishing a definitive edition of Bentham's writings.UCL now endeavours to acknowledge Bentham's influence on its foundation, while avoiding any suggestion of direct involvement, by describing him as its "spiritual founder".

Bibliography

File:19 York Street, Westminster (1848).jpg|thumb|The back of No. 19, York Street (1848). In 1651 John Milton moved into a "pretty garden-house" in Petty France. He lived there until the Restoration. Later it became No. 19 York Street, belonged to Jeremy Bentham (who for a time lived next door), was occupied successively by James Mill and Stephen|1894|p=32}}{{sfn|Grayling|2013|loc="19 York Street" }}File:Jeremy Bentham House.jpg|thumb|upright|Jeremy Bentham House in Bethnal Green, East LondonEast LondonBentham was an obsessive writer and reviser, but was constitutionally incapable, except on rare occasions, of bringing his work to completion and publication.{{sfn|Lucas|Sheeran|2006| pp= 26–27}} Most of what appeared in print in his lifetime (see list of published works online) was prepared for publication by others. Several of his works first appeared in French translation, prepared for the press by Étienne Dumont, for example, Theory of Legislation, Volume 2 (Principles of the Penal Code) 1840, Weeks, Jordan, & Company. Boston. Some made their first appearance in English in the 1820s as a result of back-translation from Dumont's 1802 collection (and redaction) of Bentham's writing on civil and penal legislation.

Publications

  • WIKISOURCE, Panopticon or the Inspection-House, Panopticon or the Inspection-House, Jeremy, Bentham, 1787, harv,
  • BOOK, harv, Bentham, Jeremy, On the Liberty of the Press, and Public Discussion,weblink 1821, Hone, 0,
  • BOOK, Bentham, Jeremy, Philip, Schofield, Catherine, Pease-Watkin, Cyprian, Blamires, Rights, Representation, and Reform: Nonsense upon Stilts and Other Writings on the French Revolution, Oxford, University Press, 2002,weblink 978-0-19-924863-6, harv, 0,
  • BOOK, Bentham, Jeremy, 0,weblink Deontology or, The science of morality, John, Bowring, London, Longman, Rees, Orme, Brown, Green and Longman, 1834, Vol. 1, 101, harv,
  • JOURNAL, Gulphs in Mankind's Career of Prosperity: A Critique of Adam Smith on Interest Rate Restrictions, Bentham, Jeremy, Econ Journal Watch, Fairfax, 5, 1, Jan 2008, 66,weblink harv, 0,
  • WIKISOURCE, harv, Bentham, Jeremy, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, 1780, 0,
  • WIKISOURCE, harv, Bentham, Jeremy, A fragment on government, A fragment on government, 0, 1776, This was an unsparing criticism of some introductory passages relating to political theory in William Blackstone's Commentaries on the Laws of England. The book, published anonymously, was well received and credited to some of the greatest minds of the time. Bentham disagreed with Blackstone's defence of judge-made law, his defence of legal fictions, his theological formulation of the doctrine of mixed government, his appeal to a social contract and his use of the vocabulary of natural law. Bentham's "Fragment" was only a small part of a Commentary on the Commentaries, which remained unpublished until the twentieth century.
  • JOURNAL, Bentham, Jeremy, Crompton, Louis, Offences Against One's Self:, Journal of Homosexuality, 3, 4, 2008, 389–406, 0091-8369, 10.1300/J082v03n04_07,weblink harv, 1785, 0,
  • WIKISOURCE, Short Review of the Declaration, Short Review of the Declaration, 1776, An attack on the United States Declaration of Independence.
  • BOOK, Bentham, Jeremy, 1816, Defence of Usury; shewing the impolicy of the present legal restraints on the terms of pecuniary bargains in a letters to a friend to which is added a letter to Adam Smith, Esq. LL.D. on the discouragement opposed by the above restraints to the progress of inventive industry, 3rd, Payne & Foss, 1816, London,weblink harv, Bentham wrote a series of thirteen "Letters" addressed to Adam Smith, published in 1787 as Defence of Usury. Bentham's main argument against the restriction is that "projectors" generate positive externalities. G.K. Chesterton identified Bentham's essay on usury as the very beginning of the "modern world". Bentham's arguments were very influential. "Writers of eminence" moved to abolish the restriction, and repeal was achieved in stages and fully achieved in England in 1854. There is little evidence as to Smith's reaction. He did not revise the offending passages in The Wealth of Nations, but Smith made little or no substantial revisions after the third edition of 1784.
  • BOOK, Bentham, Jeremy, 1791, Essay on Political Tactics containing six of the Principal Rules proper to be observed by a Political Assembly In the process of a Forming a Decision: with the Reasons on Which They Are Grounded; and a comparative application of them to British and French Practice: Being a Fragment of a larger Work, a sketch of which is subjoined, First, T. Payne, 1791, London,weblink harv, 0,
  • WIKISOURCE, Bentham, Jeremy, Emancipate Your Colonies! Addressed to the National Convention of France A° 1793, shewing the uselessness and mischievousness of distant dependencies to an European state, Robert Heward, 1830, London, Emancipate your colonies!, harv, 0,
  • BOOK, Bentham, Jeremy, 1796, Anarchical Fallacies; Being an examination of the Declaration of Rights issued during the French Revolution., London,weblink 8 January 2016, 0, An attack on the Declaration of the Rights of Man decreed by the French Revolution, and critique of the natural rights philosophy underlying it.
  • Traités de législation civile et pénale (1802, edited by Étienne Dumont. 3 vols)
  • Punishments and Rewards (1811)
  • Panopticon versus New South Wales: or, the Panopticon Penitentiary System, Compared. Containing, 1. Two Letters to Lord Pelham, Secretary of State, Comparing the two Systems on the Ground of Expediency. 2. Plea for the Constitution: Representing the Illegalities involved in the Penal Colonization System. Anno 1803, printed: now first published (1812)
  • BOOK, Bentham, Jeremy, 1817, A Table of the Springs of Action .., sold by R. Hunter, 1817, London,weblink harv, 0,
  • "Swear Not At All" (1817)
  • BOOK, Bentham, Jeremy, 1817, Plan of Parliamentary Reform, in the form of Catechism with Reasons for Each Article, with An Introduction shewing the Necessity and the Inadequacy of Moderate Reform, R. Hunter, successor to Mr. Johnson, 1817, London,weblink harv, 0,
  • BOOK, Bentham, Jeremy, 1818, Church-of-Englandism and its Catechism Examined: Preceded by the Structures on the Exclusionary System, as pursued in the National Society of Schools: Interspersed with Parallel Views of the English and Scottish Established and Non-Established Churches: And Concluding with Remedies Proposed for Abuses Indicated: and An Examination of the Parliamentary System of Church Reform Lately Pursued, and Still Pursuing: Including the Proposed New Churches, Effingham Wilson, 1818, London,weblink harv, 0,
  • BOOK, Bentham, Jeremy, 1821, The Elements of the Art of Packing, as applied to special juries particularly in cases of libel law, Effingham Wilson, 1821, London,weblink harv, 0,
  • The Influence of Natural Religion upon the Temporal Happiness of Mankind (1822, written with George Grote and published under the pseudonym Philip Beauchamp)
  • Not Paul But Jesus (1823, published under the pseudonym Gamaliel Smith)
  • BOOK, 0, Jeremy, Bentham, 1824, The Book of Fallacies from Unfinished Papers of Jeremy Bentham, First, John and H.L. Hunt, 1824, London,weblink harv,
  • BOOK, 1825, Dumont, M., A Treatise on Judicial Evidence Extracted from the Manuscripts of Jeremy Bentham, Esq, 1st, Baldwin, Cradock, & Joy, London,weblink harv, 0, Jeremy, Bentham,
  • BOOK, 0, Jeremy, Bentham, 1827, Rationale of Judicial Evidence, specially applied to English Practice, Extracted from the Manuscripts of Jeremy Bentham, Esq, I, First, Hunt & Clarke, London,weblink harv,

Posthumous publications

On his death, Bentham left manuscripts amounting to an estimated 30 million words, which are now largely held by UCL's Special Collections (c. 60,000 manuscript folios) and the British Library (c.15,000 folios).

Bowring (1838–1843)

John Bowring, the young radical writer who had been Bentham's intimate friend and disciple, was appointed his literary executor and charged with the task of preparing a collected edition of his works. This appeared in 11 volumes in 1838–1843. Bowring based much of his edition on previously published texts (including those of Dumont) rather than Bentham's own manuscripts, and elected not to publish Bentham's works on religion at all. The edition was described by the Edinburgh Review on first publication as "incomplete, incorrect and ill-arranged", and has since been repeatedly criticised both for its omissions and for errors of detail; while Bowring's memoir of Bentham's life included in volumes 10 and 11 was described by Sir Leslie Stephen as "one of the worst biographies in the language".{{sfn|Bartle|1963|p=27}} Nevertheless, Bowring's remained the standard edition of most of Bentham's writings for over a century, and is still only partially superseded: it includes such interesting writings on international{{efn|a word Bentham himself coined}} relations as Bentham's A Plan for an Universal and Perpetual Peace written 1786–89, which forms part IV of the Principles of International Law.

Stark (1952–1954)

In 1952–1954, Werner Stark published a three-volume set, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, in which he attempted to bring together all of Bentham's writings on economic matters, including both published and unpublished material. Although a significant achievement, the work is considered by scholars to be flawed in many points of detail,{{sfn|Schofield|2009a|pp=475-494}} and a new edition of the economic writings is currently in preparation by the Bentham Project.

Bentham Project (1968–present)

{{further|Transcribe Bentham}}In 1959, the Bentham Committee was established under the auspices of University College London with the aim of producing a definitive edition of Bentham's writings. It set up the Bentham Project to undertake the task, and the first volume in The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham was published in 1968. The Collected Works are providing many unpublished works, as well as much-improved texts of works already published. To date, 31 volumes have appeared; the complete edition is projected to run to around seventy. The volume Of Laws in General (1970) was found to contain many errors and has been replaced by Of the Limits of the Penal Branch of Jurisprudence (2010){{sfn|Schofield|2013|p=51–70}} In June 2017, Volumes 1–5 were re-published in open access by UCL Press.{{citation needed|date=June 2018}}To assist in this task, the Bentham papers at UCL are being digitised by crowdsourcing their transcription. Transcribe Bentham is an award-winning crowdsourced manuscript transcription project, run by University College London's Bentham Project, in partnership with UCL's UCL Centre for Digital Humanities, UCL Library Services, UCL Learning and Media Services, the University of London Computer Centre, and the online community. The project was launched in September 2010 and is making freely available, via a specially designed transcription interface, digital images of UCL's vast Bentham Papers collection—which runs to some 60,000 manuscript folios—to engage the public and recruit volunteers to help transcribe the material. Volunteer-produced transcripts will contribute to the Bentham Project's production of the new edition of The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham, and will be uploaded to UCL's digital Bentham Papers repository, widening access to the collection for all and ensuring its long-term preservation. Manuscripts can be viewed and transcribed by signing-up for a transcriber account at the Transcription Desk, via the Transcribe Bentham website.

Legacy

The Faculty of Laws at University College London occupies Bentham House, next to the main UCL campus.Bentham's name was adopted by the Australian litigation funder IMF Limited to become Bentham IMF Limited on 28 November 2013, in recognition of Bentham being "among the first to support the utility of litigation funding".

See also

  • {{annotated link|List of civil rights leaders}}
  • {{annotated link|List of liberal theorists}}
  • {{annotated link|Philosophy of happiness}}
  • {{annotated link|Rule according to higher law}}
  • {{annotated link|Rule of law}}
{{clear}}

Notes

{{notelist}}

References

  • BOOK, harv, Armitage, David, The Declaration of Independence: A Global History,weblink 2007, Harvard University Press, 978-0-674-02282-9,
  • JOURNAL, Bartle, G. F., Jeremy Bentham and John Bowring: a study of the relationship between Bentham and the editor of his Collected Works, Bulletin of the Institute of Historical Research, 36, 93, 1963, 27–35, 10.1111/j.1468-2281.1963.tb00620.x, harv,
  • JOURNAL, Bedau, Hugo Adam, Bentham's Utilitarian Critique of the Death Penalty, The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 74, 1983, 3, 1033–65, 10.2307/1143143, harv,weblink 1143143,
  • JOURNAL, Benthall, Jonathan, Animal liberation and rights, Anthropology Today, 23, 2, 2007, 1–3, 0268-540X, 10.1111/j.1467-8322.2007.00494.x, JOURNAL, Burns, J. H., Happiness and Utility: Jeremy Bentham's Equation, Utilitas, 17, 01, 2005, 46–61, 0953-8208, 10.1017/S0953820804001396, harv,
  • JOURNAL, Burns, J. H., Bentham and Blackstone: A Lifetime's Dialectic, 1989, Utilitas, 1, 22, 10.1017/S0953820800000042, harv,
  • BOOK, harv, Campos Boralevi, Lea, Bentham and the Oppressed,weblink 2012, Walter de Gruyter, 978-3-11-086983-5,
  • BOOK, Crimmins, James E., Bentham on Religion: Atheism and the Secular Society, 1986, University of Pennsylvania Press, 2709597, Journal of the History of Ideas, 47, 1, 95–110, 10.2307/2709597, harv,
  • BOOK, harv, Crimmins, James E., Secular Utilitarianism: Social Science and the Critique of Religion in the Thought of Jeremy Bentham,weblink 1990, Clarendon Press, 978-0-19-827741-5,
  • BOOK, harv, Cutrofello, Andrew, All for Nothing: Hamlet's Negativity,weblink 2014, MIT Press, 978-0-262-52634-0,
  • BOOK, Dinwiddy, John, 2004, Bentham: selected writings of John Dinwiddy, Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA, 978-0-8047-4520-8,
  • BOOK, Dupont, Christian Y., Onuf, Peter S., Declaring Independence: The Origin and Influence of America's Founding Document : Featuring the Albert H. Small Declaration of Independence Collection,weblink 2008, University of Virginia Library, Charlottesville, VA, 978-0-9799997-0-3, harv,
  • BOOK, Everett, Charles Warren, Jeremy Bentham, London, Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1969, 0297179845, 157781, harv,
  • BOOK, harv, Follett, R., Evangelicalism, Penal Theory and the Politics of Criminal Law: Reform in England, 1808-30,weblink 2000, Palgrave Macmillan, 978-1-4039-3276-1,
  • BOOK, Michel, Foucault, Discipline and Punish: the Birth of the Prison, Alan Sheridan, Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1977, 9780140137224, harv, Michel Foucault,weblink
  • BOOK, harv, Francione, Gary, Animals: Property or Persons, Sunstein, Cass R., Martha C., Nussbaum, Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions,weblink 2004, Oxford University Press, USA, 978-0-19-515217-3,
  • BOOK, harv, González, Ana Marta, Contemporary Perspectives on Natural Law: Natural Law as a Limiting Concept,weblink 2012, Ashgate Publishing, 978-1-4094-8566-7,
  • BOOK, Grayling, A. C., A. C. Grayling, 2013, 19 York Street, The Quarrel of the Age: The Life and Times Of William Hazlitt,weblink harv,
  • WEB, Gruen, Lori,weblink The Moral Status of Animals, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1 July 2003, harv,
  • BOOK, Gunn, J. A. W., 1989, Jeremy Bentham and the Public Interest, J., Lively, A., Reeve, Modern Political Theory from Hobbes to Marx: Key Debates, London, 199–219,
  • BOOK, harv, Hamburger, Joseph, Intellectuals in Politics: John Stuart Mill and the Philosophic Radicals,weblink 1965, Yale University Press,
  • JOURNAL, Harris, Jonathan, 1998, Bernardino Rivadavia and Benthamite 'discipleship', Latin American Research Review, 33, 129–49, harv,
  • BOOK, Harrison, Ross, 1983, Bentham, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 0-7100-9526-0,
  • BOOK, Harrison, Ross,weblink Jeremy Bentham, Honderich, Ted, The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 1995, 85–88, harv,
  • JOURNAL, Hart, Jenifer, Nineteenth-Century Social Reform: A Tory Interpretation of History, Past & Present, 31, July 1965, 39–61, 650101, harv,
  • BOOK, Harte, Negley, The owner of share no. 633: Jeremy Bentham and University College London, Catherine, Fuller, The Old Radical: representations of Jeremy Bentham, London, University College London, 1998, harv,
  • BOOK, Himmelfarb, Gertrude, Victorian Minds, New York, 1968, harv,
  • BOOK, harv, Kelly, Paul J., Utilitarianism and distributive justice: Jeremy Bentham and the civil law,weblink 1990, Oxford University Press, 978-0-19-825418-8,
  • BOOK, Anonymous, An Answer to the Declaration of the American Congress,weblink London, T. Cadell, 1776, harv,
  • JOURNAL, Lucas, Philip, Sheeran, Anne, Asperger's Syndrome and the Eccentricity and Genius of Jeremy Bentham, Journal of Bentham Studies, 8, 2006,weblink harv,
  • JOURNAL, Andrew P., Morriss, Codification and Right Answers, 74, Chic.-Kent L. Rev., 355, 1999, harv,weblink
  • BOOK, harv, McStay, Andrew, Privacy and Philosophy: New Media and Affective Protocol,weblink 2014, Peter Lang, 978-1-4331-1898-2,
  • BOOK, Murphy, James Bernard, The Philosophy of Customary Law,weblink 2014, Oxford University Press, 978-0-19-937062-7, harv,
  • BOOK, harv, Packe, Michael St. John, The Life of John Stuart Mill,weblink London, Secker and Warburg, 1954,
  • JOURNAL, Persky, Joseph, 1 January 2007, Retrospectives: From Usury to Interest, The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 21, 1, 228, 10.1257/jep.21.1.227, 30033709, harv,
  • BOOK, harv, Postema, Gerald J., Bentham and the Common Law Tradition,weblink 1986, Oxford U. P., 978-0-19-825505-5,
  • BOOK, Priestley, Joseph, Joseph Priestley, An Essay on the First Principles of Government: And on the Nature of Political, Civil, and Religious Liberty,weblink London, J. Johnson, 1771, harv,
  • BOOK, Roberts, Clayton, Roberts, David F., Bisson, Douglas, A History of England, Volume II: 1688 to the Present,weblink 2016, 307, Routledge, 978-1-315-50960-0, 6th, London and New York, harv,
  • BOOK, Robinson, Dave, Groves, Judy, 2003, Introducing Political Philosophy, Cambridge, Icon Books, 1-84046-450-X,
  • BOOK, Rosen, F., 1983, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy: A Study of the "Constitutional Code", Oxford, Clarendon Press, 0-19-822656-X,
  • BOOK, Rosen, Frederick, 1990, The Origins of Liberal Utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham and Liberty, R., Bellamy, Victorian Liberalism: Nineteenth-century Political Thought and Practice, London, 5870,
  • BOOK, Rosen, Frederick, 1992, Bentham, Byron, and Greece: constitutionalism, nationalism, and early liberal political thought, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 0-19-820078-1,
  • BOOK, Rosen, Frederick, 2007, Jeremy Bentham, Aldershot, Ashgate, 978-0-7546-2566-7,
  • BOOK, Schofield, Philip, Utility and Democracy: The Political Thought of Jeremy Bentham, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006, 978-0-19-820856-3,
  • BOOK, Schofield, Philip, Bentham: a guide for the perplexed, 2009, London, Continuum, 978-0-8264-9589-1, harv,
  • JOURNAL, Schofield, Philip, Werner Stark and Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, History of European Ideas, 35, 4, 2009, 475–94, 10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2009.05.003, harv,
  • JOURNAL, Schofield, Philip, The Legal and Political Legacy of Jeremy Bentham, Annual Review of Law and Social Science, 9, 1, 2013, 51–70, 10.1146/annurev-lawsocsci-102612-134101, harv,
  • BOOK, Semple, Janet, Bentham's Prison: a Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1993, 0-19-827387-8,
  • BOOK, Spiegel, Henry William, The Growth of Economic Thought,weblink 3rd, 1991, Duke University Press, 0-8223-0973-4, harv,
  • DNB, Stephen, Leslie, Milton, John (1608-1674), Milton, John (1608–1674), 38, 32, harv,
  • BOOK, Sunstein, Cass R., Animal Rights, Sunstein, Cass R., Martha C., Nussbaum, Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions,weblink 2004, Oxford University Press, USA, 978-0-19-515217-3, harv,
  • BOOK, Thomas, William, The Philosophic Radicals: Nine Studies in Theory and Practice, 1817-1841,weblink 1979, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 978-0-19-822490-7, harv,
  • BOOK, Twining, William, 1985, Theories of Evidence: Bentham and Wigmore, Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA, 0-8047-1285-9,
  • JOURNAL, Vergara, Francisco,weblink A Critique of Elie Halévy; refutation of an important distortion of British moral philosophy, Philosophy, Royal Institute of Philosophy, London, 1998, 73, 1, 97–111, harv,
  • JOURNAL, Vergara, Francisco,weblink Bentham and Mill on the "Quality" of Pleasures, Revue d'études benthamiennes, Paris, 2011, 1760-7507, harv,
  • JOURNAL, Williford, Miriam, Bentham on the Rights of Women, Journal of the History of Ideas, 36, 1, 1975, 167, 0022-5037, 10.2307/2709019, harv,

Further reading

External links

{{commons}}{{wikisource author}} {{University College London|university}}{{Classical economists}}{{Age of Enlightenment}}{{Social and political philosophy}}{{Ethics}}{{jurisprudence}}{{liberalism}}{{animal rights|state=collapsed}}{{Authority control}}

- content above as imported from Wikipedia
- "Jeremy Bentham" does not exist on GetWiki (yet)
- time: 4:16pm EDT - Mon, Jun 24 2019
[ this remote article is provided by Wikipedia ]
LATEST EDITS [ see all ]
GETWIKI 09 MAY 2016
GETWIKI 18 OCT 2015
M.R.M. Parrott
Biographies
GETWIKI 20 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 19 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 18 AUG 2014
Wikinfo
Culture
CONNECT