SUPPORT THE WORK

GetWiki

Bayes' theorem

ARTICLE SUBJECTS
aesthetics  →
being  →
complexity  →
database  →
enterprise  →
ethics  →
fiction  →
history  →
internet  →
knowledge  →
language  →
licensing  →
linux  →
logic  →
method  →
news  →
perception  →
philosophy  →
policy  →
purpose  →
religion  →
science  →
sociology  →
software  →
truth  →
unix  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE TYPES
essay  →
feed  →
help  →
system  →
wiki  →
ARTICLE ORIGINS
critical  →
discussion  →
forked  →
imported  →
original  →
Bayes' theorem
[ temporary import ]
please note:
- the content below is remote from Wikipedia
- it has been imported raw for GetWiki
{{redirect|Bayes rule|the concept in decision theory|Bayes estimator}}{{short description|Probability based on prior knowledge}}File:Bayes' Theorem MMB 01.jpg|thumb|A blue neon signneon sign{{Bayesian statistics}}In probability theory and statistics, Bayes' theorem (alternatively Bayes' law or Bayes' rule) describes the probability of an event, based on prior knowledge of conditions that might be related to the event. For example, if cancer is related to age, then, using Bayes' theorem, a person's age can be used to more accurately assess the probability that they have cancer, compared to the assessment of the probability of cancer made without knowledge of the person's age.One of the many applications of Bayes' theorem is Bayesian inference, a particular approach to statistical inference. When applied, the probabilities involved in Bayes' theorem may have different probability interpretations. With the Bayesian probability interpretation the theorem expresses how a subjective degree of belief should rationally change to account for availability of related evidence. Bayesian inference is fundamental to Bayesian statistics.Bayes' theorem is named after Reverend Thomas Bayes ({{IPAc-en|b|eɪ|z}}; 1701–1761), who first provided an equation that allows new evidence to update beliefs in his An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances (1763). It was further developed by Pierre-Simon Laplace, who first published the modern formulation in his 1812 "Théorie analytique des probabilités". Sir Harold Jeffreys put Bayes' algorithm and Laplace's formulation on an axiomatic basis. Jeffreys wrote that Bayes' theorem "is to the theory of probability what the Pythagorean theorem is to geometry".BOOK, Jeffreys, Harold, Harold Jeffreys, 1973, Scientific Inference, Cambridge University Press, 3rd, 978-0-521-18078-8, 31,

Statement of theorem

File:Bayes' Theorem 2D.svg|thumb|Visualization of Bayes' theorem by superposition of two event tree diagrams.]]Bayes' theorem is stated mathematically as the following equation:{{Citation | first1= A. | last1= Stuart | first2= K. | last2= Ord | title= Kendall's Advanced Theory of Statistics: Volume I—Distribution Theory | year= 1994 | publisher= Edward Arnold | at= §8.7}}
P(Amid B) = frac{P(B mid A) , P(A)}{P(B)},
where A and B are events and P(B) neq 0.
  • P(Amid B) is a conditional probability: the likelihood of event A occurring given that B is true.
  • P(Bmid A) is also a conditional probability: the likelihood of event B occurring given that A is true.
  • P(A) and P(B) are the probabilities of observing A and B independently of each other; this is known as the marginal probability.

Examples

Drug testing

(File:Bayes theorem drugs example tree.svg|thumb|Tree diagram illustrating drug testing example. U, Ū, "+" and "−" are the events representing user, non-user, positive result and negative result. Percentages in parentheses are calculated.)Suppose that a test for using a particular drug is 99% sensitive and 99% specific. That is, the test will produce 99% true positive results for drug users and 99% true negative results for non-drug users. Suppose that 0.5% of people are users of the drug. What is the probability that a randomly selected individual with a positive test is a drug user?
begin{align}P(text{User}midtext{+}) &= frac{P(text{+}midtext{User}) P(text{User})}{P(+)}
&= frac{P(text{+}midtext{User}) P(text{User})}{P(text{+}midtext{User}) P(text{User}) + P(text{+}midtext{Non-user}) P(text{Non-user})} [8pt]
&= frac{0.99 times 0.005}{0.99 times 0.005 + 0.01 times 0.995} [8pt]&approx 33.2%end{align}Even if an individual tests positive, it is more likely that they do not use the drug than that they do. This is because the number of non-users is large compared to the number of users. The number of false positives outweighs the number of true positives. For example, if 1000 individuals are tested, there are expected to be 995 non-users and 5 users. From the 995 non-users, 0.01 Ã— 995 â‰ƒ 10 false positives are expected. From the 5 users, 0.99 Ã— 5 â‰ˆ 5 true positives are expected. Out of 15 positive results, only 5 are genuine.The importance of specificity in this example can be seen by calculating that even if sensitivity is raised to 100% and specificity remains at 99% then the probability of the person being a drug user only rises from 33.2% to 33.4%, but if the sensitivity is held at 99% and the specificity is increased to 99.5% then the probability of the person being a drug user rises to about 49.9%.

A more complicated example

The entire output of a factory is produced on three machines. The three machines account for 20%, 30%, and 50% of the factory output. The fraction of defective items produced is 5% for the first machine; 3% for the second machine; and 1% for the third machine. If an item is chosen at random from the total output and is found to be defective, what is the probability that it was produced by the third machine?Once again, the answer can be reached without recourse to the formula by applying the conditions to any hypothetical number of cases. For example, if 100,000 items are produced by the factory, 20,000 will be produced by Machine A, 30,000 by Machine B, and 50,000 by Machine C. Machine A will produce 1000 defective items, Machine B 900, and Machine C 500. Of the total 2400 defective items, only 500, or 5/24 were produced by Machine C.A solution is as follows. Let Xi denote the event that a randomly chosen item was made by the i th machine (for i = A,B,C). Let Y denote the event that a randomly chosen item is defective. Then, we are given the following information:
P(XA) = 0.2,    P(XB) = 0.3,    P(XC) = 0.5.
If the item was made by the first machine, then the probability that it is defective is 0.05; that is, P(Y | XA) = 0.05. Overall, we have
P(Y | XA) = 0.05,    P(Y | XB) = 0.03,    P(Y | XC) = 0.01.
To answer the original question, we first find P(Y). That can be done in the following way:
P(Y) = Σi P(Y | Xi) P(Xi) = (0.05)(0.2) + (0.03)(0.3) + (0.01)(0.5) = 0.024.
Hence 2.4% of the total output of the factory is defective.We are given that Y has occurred, and we want to calculate the conditionalprobability of XC. By Bayes' theorem,
P(XC | Y) = {{sfrac|P(Y {{!}} XC) P(XC)|P(Y)}} = {{sfrac|(0.01)(0.50)|0.024}} = {{sfrac|5|24}}.
Given that the item is defective, the probability that it was made by the thirdmachine is only 5/24. Although machine C produces half of the total output, itproduces a much smaller fraction of the defective items. Hence the knowledgethat the item selected was defective enables us to replace the prior probabilityP(XC) = 1/2 by the smaller posterior probability P(XC | Y) = 5/24.

Interpretations

(File:Bayes theorem visualisation.svg|thumb|192px|A geometric visualisation of Bayes' theorem. The figures denote the cells of the table involved in each metric, the probability being the fraction of each figure that is shaded. Similar reasoning shows thatbegin{smallmatrix}P(bar{A}mid B),=,frac{P(Bmidbar{A}),P(bar{A})}{P(B)}end{smallmatrix}and so on.)The interpretation of Bayes' theorem depends on the interpretation of probability ascribed to the terms. The two main interpretations are described below.

Bayesian interpretation

In the Bayesian (or epistemological) interpretation, probability measures a "degree of belief." Bayes' theorem then links the degree of belief in a proposition before and after accounting for evidence. For example, suppose it is believed with 50% certainty that a coin is twice as likely to land heads than tails. If the coin is flipped a number of times and the outcomes observed, that degree of belief may rise, fall or remain the same depending on the results.For proposition A and evidence B,
* P (A ), the prior, is the initial degree of belief in A. * P (A | B ), the posterior is the degree of belief having accounted for B. * the quotient {{sfrac|P(B {{!}}A )|P(B)}} represents the support B provides for A.
For more on the application of Bayes' theorem under the Bayesian interpretation of probability, see Bayesian inference.

Frequentist interpretation

File:Bayes theorem tree diagrams.svg|thumb|Illustration of frequentist interpretation with tree diagrams. Bayes' theorem connects conditional probabilities to their inverses.]]In the frequentist interpretation, probability measures a "proportion of outcomes." For example, suppose an experiment is performed many times. P(A) is the proportion of outcomes with property A, and P(B) that with property B. P(B | A ) is the proportion of outcomes with property B out of outcomes with property A, and P(A | B ) the proportion of those with A out of those with B.The role of Bayes' theorem is best visualized with tree diagrams, as shown to the right. The two diagrams partition the same outcomes by A and B in opposite orders, to obtain the inverse probabilities. Bayes' theorem serves as the link between these different partitionings.

Example

(File:Bayes theorem simple example tree.svg|thumb|Tree diagram illustrating frequentist example. R, C, P and P bar are the events representing rare, common, pattern and no pattern. Percentages in parentheses are calculated. Note that three independent values are given, so it is possible to calculate the inverse tree (see figure above).)An entomologist spots what might be a rare subspecies of beetle, due to the pattern on its back. In the rare subspecies, 98% have the pattern, or P(Pattern | Rare) = 98%. In the common subspecies, 5% have the pattern. The rare subspecies accounts for only 0.1% of the population. How likely is the beetle having the pattern to be rare, or what is P(Rare | Pattern)?From the extended form of Bayes' theorem (since any beetle can be only rare or common),
begin{align}
P(text{Rare}mid text{Pattern}) &= frac{P(text{Pattern}mid text{Rare})P(text{Rare})} {P(text{Pattern})}[8pt] &= frac{P(text{Pattern}mid text{Rare})P(text{Rare})} {P(text{Pattern}mid text{Rare}) P(text{Rare}) + P(text{Pattern}mid text{Common})P(text{Common})}[8pt] &= frac{0.98 times 0.001} {0.98 times 0.001 + 0.05 times 0.999}[8pt] &approx 1.9%end{align}

Forms

Events

Simple form

For events A and B, provided that P(B) â‰  0,
P(Amid B) = frac{P(B mid A), P(A)}{P(B)}cdot
In many applications, for instance in Bayesian inference, the event B is fixed in the discussion, and we wish to consider the impact of its having been observed on our belief in various possible events A. In such a situation the denominator of the last expression, the probability of the given evidence B, is fixed; what we want to vary is A. Bayes' theorem then shows that the posterior probabilities are proportional to the numerator:
P(Amid B) propto P(A) cdot P(Bmid A) (proportionality over A for given B).
The posterior is proportional to the prior times the likelihood.BOOK
, Lee
, Peter M.
, Bayesian Statistics
,weblink
, John Wiley & Sons, Wiley
, 2012
, 978-1-1183-3257-3
, Chapter 1
, If events A1, A2, ..., are mutually exclusive and exhaustive, i.e., one of them is certain to occur but no two can occur together, and we know their probabilities up to proportionality, then we can determine the proportionality constant by using the fact that their probabilities must add up to one. For instance, for a given event A, the event A itself and its complement ¬A are exclusive and exhaustive. Denoting the constant of proportionality by c we have
P(Amid B) = c cdot P(A) cdot P(Bmid A) text{ and } P(neg Amid B) = c cdot P(neg A) cdot P(Bmid neg A).
Adding these two formulas we deduce that
1 = c cdot (P(Bmid A)cdot P(A) + P(Bmid neg A) cdot P(neg A)),
or
c = frac{1}{P(Bmid A)cdot P(A) + P(Bmid neg A) cdot P(neg A)} = frac 1 {P(B)}.

Alternative form

Another form of Bayes' Theorem that is generally encountered when looking at two competing statements or hypotheses is:
P(Amid B) = frac{P(Bmid A),P(A)}{ P(Bmid A) P(A) + P(Bmid neg A) P(neg A)}.
For an epistemological interpretation:For proposition A and evidence or background B,WEB, Bayes' Theorem: Introduction,weblink Trinity University,
  • P(A) is the prior probability, is the initial degree of belief in A.
  • P(neg A) is the corresponding probability of the initial degree of belief against A, where 1-P(A) = P(neg A)
  • P(Bmid A) is the conditional probability or likelihood, is the degree of belief in B, given that the proposition A is true.
  • P(Bmidneg A) is the conditional probability or likelihood, is the degree of belief in B, given that the proposition neg A is true.
  • P(Amid B) is the posterior probability, is the probability for A after taking into account B for and against A.

Extended form

Often, for some partition {Aj} of the sample space, the event space is given or conceptualized in terms of P(Aj) and P(B | Aj). It is then useful to compute P(B) using the law of total probability:
P(B) = {sum_j P(Bmid A_j) P(A_j)}, Rightarrow P(A_imid B) = frac{P(Bmid A_i),P(A_i)}{sumlimits_j P(Bmid A_j),P(A_j)}cdot
In the special case where A is a binary variable:
P(Amid B) = frac{P(Bmid A),P(A)}{ P(Bmid A) P(A) + P(Bmid neg A) P(neg A)}cdot

Random variables

File:Bayes continuous diagram.svg|thumb|Diagram illustrating the meaning of Bayes' theorem as applied to an event space generated by continuous random variables X and Y. Note that there exists an instance of Bayes' theorem for each point in the domain. In practice, these instances might be parametrized by writing the specified probability densities as a function of x and y.]]Consider a sample space Ω generated by two random variables X and Y. In principle, Bayes' theorem applies to the events A = {X = x} and B = {Y = y}. However, terms become 0 at points where either variable has finite probability density. To remain useful, Bayes' theorem may be formulated in terms of the relevant densities (see Derivation).

Simple form

If X is continuous and Y is discrete,
f_{X,mid,Y=y}(x) = frac{P(Y=ymid X=x),f_X(x)}{P(Y=y)}
where each f is a density function.If X is discrete and Y is continuous,
P(X=xmid Y=y) = frac{f_{Y,mid,X=x}(y),P(X=x)}{f_Y(y)}.
If both X and Y are continuous,
f_{X,mid,Y=y}(x) = frac{f_{Y,mid,X=x}(y),f_X(x)}{f_Y(y)}.

Extended form

(File:Continuous event space specification.svg|thumb|Diagram illustrating how an event space generated by continuous random variables X and Y is often conceptualized.)A continuous event space is often conceptualized in terms of the numerator terms. It is then useful to eliminate the denominator using the law of total probability. For fY(y), this becomes an integral:
f_Y(y) = int_{-infty}^infty f_Y(ymid X=xi ),f_X(xi),dxi .

Bayes' rule

Bayes' theorem in odds form is:
O(A_1:A_2mid B) = O(A_1:A_2) cdot Lambda(A_1:A_2mid B)
where
Lambda(A_1:A_2mid B) = frac{P(Bmid A_1)}{P(Bmid A_2)}
is called the Bayes factor or likelihood ratio and the odds between two events is simply the ratio of the probabilities of the two events. Thus
O(A_1:A_2) = frac{P(A_1)}{P(A_2)},
O(A_1:A_2mid B) = frac{P(A_1mid B)}{P(A_2mid B)},
So the rule says that the posterior odds are the prior odds times the Bayes factor, or in other words, posterior is proportional to prior times likelihood.

Derivation

For events

Bayes' theorem may be derived from the definition of conditional probability:
P(Amid B)=frac{P(A cap B)}{P(B)}, text{ if } P(B) neq 0, P(Bmid A) = frac{P(B cap A)}{P(A)}, text{ if } P(A) neq 0,
where P(A cap B) is the joint probability of both A and B being true, because
P(B cap A)=P(A cap B) Rightarrow P(A cap B) = P(Amid B), P(B) = P(Bmid A), P(A) Rightarrow P(Amid B) = frac{P(Bmid A),P(A)}{P(B)}, text{ if } P(B) neq 0.

For random variables

For two continuous random variables X and Y, Bayes' theorem may be analogously derived from the definition of conditional density:
f_{X,mid, Y=y} (x) = frac{f_{X,Y}(x,y)}{f_Y(y)} f_{Y,mid, X=x}(y) = frac{f_{X,Y}(x,y)}{f_X(x)}
Therefore
f_{X,mid,Y=y}(x) = frac{f_{Y,mid, X=x}(y),f_X(x)}{f_Y(y)}.

Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks

Propositional logic

Bayes' theorem represents a generalisation of contraposition which in propositional logic can be expressed as:
(lnot A to lnot B) to (B to A).
The corresponding formula in terms of probability calculus is Bayes' theorem which in its expanded form is expressed as:
P(A mid B) = frac{P(B mid A),a(A)}{P(Bmid A),a(A)+P(B mid lnot A),a(lnot A)}.
In the equation above the conditional probability P(B mid A) generalizes the logical statement (A to B), i.e. in addition to assigning TRUE or FALSE we can also assign any probability to the statement. The term a(A) denotes the prior probability (aka. the base rate) of A. Assume that P(A mid B) = 1 is equivalent to (B to A) being TRUE, and that P(A mid B) = 0 is equivalent to (B to A) being FALSE. It is then easy to see that P(A mid B) = 1 when P(lnot Bmid lnot A) = 1 i.e. when (lnot A to lnot B) is TRUE. This is because P(Bmid lnot A) = 1 - P(lnot B mid lnot A) = 0 so that the fraction on the right-hand side of the equation above is equal to 1, and hence P(A mid B) = 1 which is equivalent to (B to A) being TRUE. Hence, Bayes' theorem represents a generalization of contraposition.Audun Jøsang, 2016, Subjective Logic; A formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty. Springer, Cham, {{ISBN|978-3-319-42337-1}}

Subjective logic

Bayes' theorem represents a special case of conditional inversion in subjective logic expressed as:
(omega^S_{Atilde{|}B},omega^S_{Atilde{|}lnot B}) = (omega^S_{Bmid A}, omega^S_{Bmidlnot A}),widetilde{phi,}, a_A,,
where ,widetilde{phi,}, denotes the operator for conditional inversion. The argument (omega^S_{Bmid A},omega^S_{Bmidlnot A}) denotes a pair of binomial conditional opinions, as expressed by source S, and the argument a_{A} denotes the prior probability (aka. the base rate) of A. The pair of inverted conditional opinions is denoted (omega^S_{Atilde{|}B},omega^{S}_{Atilde{|}lnot B}). The conditional opinion omega^S_{Amid B} generalizes the probabilistic conditional P(A mid B), i.e. in addition to assigning a probability the source S can assign any subjective opinion to the conditional statement (Amid B). A binomial subjective opinion omega^{S}_{A} is the belief in the truth of statement A with degrees of uncertainty, as expressed by source S. Every subjective opinion has a corresponding projected probability P(omega^{S}_{A}). The projected probability of opinions applied to Bayes' theorem produces a homomorphism so that Bayes' theorem can be expressed in terms of the projected probabilities of opinions:
P(omega^S_{A tilde{|} B}) = frac{P(omega^S_{B mid A}),a(A)}{P(omega^S_{Bmid A}) , a(A) + P(omega^S_{B mid lnot A}),a(lnot A)}.
Hence, the subjective Bayes' theorem represents a generalization of Bayes' theorem.Audun Jøsang, 2016, Generalising Bayes' Theorem in Subjective Logic. IEEE International Conference on Multisensor Fusion and Integration for Intelligent Systems (MFI 2016), Baden-Baden, September 2016

History

Bayes' theorem was named after Thomas Bayes (1701–1761), who studied how to compute a distribution for the probability parameter of a binomial distribution (in modern terminology). Bayes' unpublished manuscript was significantly edited by Richard Price before it was posthumously read at the Royal Society. Price editedBOOK, Richard Allen, David Hartley on Human Nature,weblink 16 June 2013, 1999, SUNY Press, 978-0-7914-9451-6, 243–4, Bayes' major work "An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances" (1763), which appeared in Philosophical Transactions,JOURNAL, 10.1098/rstl.1763.0053, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 53, 0, 1763, 370–418,weblink An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chance. By the late Rev. Mr. Bayes, communicated by Mr. Price, in a letter to John Canton, A. M. F. R. S., Bayes, Thomas, Price, Richard, yes, and contains Bayes' Theorem. Price wrote an introduction to the paper which provides some of the philosophical basis of Bayesian statistics. In 1765, he was elected a Fellow of the Royal Society in recognition of his work on the legacy of Bayes.Holland, pp. 46–7.BOOK, Richard Price, Price: Political Writings,weblink 16 June 2013, 1991, Cambridge University Press, 978-0-521-40969-8, xxiii, The French mathematician Pierre-Simon Laplace reproduced and extended Bayes' results in 1774, apparently unaware of Bayes' work.Laplace refined Bayes' theorem over a period of decades:
  • Laplace announced his independent discovery of Bayes' theorem in: Laplace (1774) "Mémoire sur la probabilité des causes par les événements," "Mémoires de l'Académie royale des Sciences de MI (Savants étrangers)," 4: 621–656. Reprinted in: Laplace, "Oeuvres complètes" (Paris, France: Gauthier-Villars et fils, 1841), vol. 8, pp. 27–65. Available on-line at: Gallica. Bayes' theorem appears on p. 29.
  • Laplace presented a refinement of Bayes' theorem in: Laplace (read: 1783 / published: 1785) "Mémoire sur les approximations des formules qui sont fonctions de très grands nombres," "Mémoires de l'Académie royale des Sciences de Paris," 423–467. Reprinted in: Laplace, "Oeuvres complètes" (Paris, France: Gauthier-Villars et fils, 1844), vol. 10, pp. 295–338. Available on-line at: Gallica. Bayes' theorem is stated on page 301.
  • See also: Laplace, "Essai philosophique sur les probabilités" (Paris, France: Mme. Ve. Courcier [Madame veuve (i.e., widow) Courcier], 1814), page 10. English translation: Pierre Simon, Marquis de Laplace with F. W. Truscott and F. L. Emory, trans., "A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities" (New York, New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1902), page 15.BOOK, Classical Probability in the Enlightenment, Lorraine, Daston, Princeton Univ Press, 1988, 268, 0-691-08497-1,weblink The Bayesian interpretation of probability was developed mainly by Laplace.Stigler, Stephen M. (1986). The History of Statistics: The Measurement of Uncertainty before 1900. Harvard University Press, Chapter 3.
Stephen Stigler suggested in 1983 that Bayes' theorem was discovered by Nicholas Saunderson, a blind English mathematician, some time before Bayes;JOURNAL, Stigler, Stephen M, 1983, Who Discovered Bayes' Theorem?, The American Statistician, 37, 4, 290–296, 10.1080/00031305.1983.10483122, BOOK, Stats, Data and Models, Velleman, Paul, Bock, David, 2016, Pearson, 978-0-321-98649-8, 4, 380–381, De Vaux, Richard, that interpretation, however, has been disputed.JOURNAL, Edwards, A. W. F., 1986, Is the Reference in Hartley (1749) to Bayesian Inference?, The American Statistician, 40, 2, 109–110, 10.1080/00031305.1986.10475370, Martyn HooperJOURNAL, Hooper, Martyn, 2013, Richard Price, Bayes' theorem, and God, Significance, 10, 1, 36–39, 10.1111/j.1740-9713.2013.00638.x, and Sharon McGrayneBOOK, McGrayne, S. B., The Theory That Would Not Die: How Bayes' Rule Cracked the Enigma Code, Hunted Down Russian Submarines & Emerged Triumphant from Two Centuries of Controversy, Yale University Press, 2011, 978-0-300-18822-6, have argued that Richard Price's contribution was substantial:{{block quote|By modern standards, we should refer to the Bayes–Price rule. Price discovered Bayes' work, recognized its importance, corrected it, contributed to the article, and found a use for it. The modern convention of employing Bayes' name alone is unfair but so entrenched that anything else makes little sense.}}

See also

Notes

{{reflist|30em}}

Further reading

  • Bruss, F. Thomas (2013), "250 years of 'An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chance. By the late Rev. Mr. Bayes, communicated by Mr. Price, in a letter to John Canton, A. M. F. R. S.'," {{doi|10.1365/s13291-013-0077-z}}, Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, Springer Verlag, Vol. 115, Issue 3-4 (2013), 129-133.
  • Gelman, A, Carlin, JB, Stern, HS, and Rubin, DB (2003), "Bayesian Data Analysis," Second Edition, CRC Press.
  • Grinstead, CM and Snell, JL (1997), "Introduction to Probability (2nd edition)," American Mathematical Society (free pdf available) weblink.
  • {{springer|title=Bayes formula|id=p/b015380}}
  • BOOK, McGrayne, SB, The Theory That Would Not Die: How Bayes' Rule Cracked the Enigma Code, Hunted Down Russian Submarines & Emerged Triumphant from Two Centuries of Controversy, Yale University Press, 2011, 978-0-300-18822-6,
  • Laplace, P (1774/1986), "Memoir on the Probability of the Causes of Events", Statistical Science 1(3):364–378.
  • Lee, Peter M (2012), "Bayesian Statistics: An Introduction," 4th edition. Wiley. {{ISBN|978-1-118-33257-3}}.
  • JOURNAL, 31 March 2015, Bayes' theorem,weblink Nat. Methods, Nature Methods, 12, 4, 277-278, Puga JL, Krzywinski M, Altman N,
  • Rosenthal, Jeffrey S (2005), "Struck by Lightning: The Curious World of Probabilities." HarperCollins. (Granta, 2008. {{ISBN|9781862079960}}).
  • JOURNAL, Stigler, SM, 1986, Laplace's 1774 Memoir on Inverse Probability, Statistical Science, 1, 3, 359–363, 10.1214/ss/1177013620,
  • Stone, JV (2013), download chapter 1 of "Bayes' Rule: A Tutorial Introduction to Bayesian Analysis", Sebtel Press, England.
  • Bayesian Reasoning for Intelligent People, An introduction and tutorial to the use of Bayes' theorem in statistics and cognitive science.
  • Morris, Dan (2016), Read first 6 chapters for free of "Bayes' Theorem Examples: A Visual Introduction For Beginners" Blue Windmill {{ISBN|978-1549761744}}. A short tutorial on how to understand problem scenarios and find P(B), P(A), and P(B|A).

External links



- content above as imported from Wikipedia
- "Bayes' theorem" does not exist on GetWiki (yet)
- time: 8:47pm EST - Tue, Nov 20 2018
[ this remote article is provided by Wikipedia ]
LATEST EDITS [ see all ]
GETWIKI 09 MAY 2016
GETWIKI 18 OCT 2015
M.R.M. Parrott
Biographies
GETWIKI 20 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 19 AUG 2014
GETWIKI 18 AUG 2014
Wikinfo
Culture
CONNECT